Al
Qaeda’s Foot Soldiers and the Problem of Moral Equality
“This guy Padilla is a bad guy, and he is where he needs
to be—detained.”[1]
--President G. W. Bush, in defending his decision to classify
Jose Padilla,
In the aftermath
of September 11th,
In this paper I
will argue that terrorism and its particular brand of “soldiers” pose a unique
moral challenge for
The solution the American government has arrived upon thus far from
encapsulating the moral equality that Walzer prescribes. In fact,
Characteristically,
media sources have variously attacked this policy, calling it among other
things a malicious “diluting” of the Geneva Convention[3] and a case of
“legal limbo.”[4] Legal
scholars like David Luban of
Walzer’s Argument for the Moral
Equality of Soldiers (in brief).
Michael
Walzer argues in Just and Unjust Wars that much of the moral evil of war
lies in its “tyranny,” or the moral wrong entailed by making soldiers fight and
die against their will. Soldiers most often end up fighting because their
parent states have coerced them to do so, often either through legal guidelines
or a deliberate campaign of patriotism—fighting usually for circumstances that
under normal conditions would not obviously compel them to do so. Dire
conditions of self-defense aside, states employ military force in many types of
conflicts, and need soldiers to do so. To fill the ranks, states through the
use of various agencies often employ methods that seize upon their citizens’
ideologies, legal obligations, financial desires, and patriotism in order to
obtain their services. When states employ these methods, Walzer argues
that the conditions for decision that ensue for citizens virtually eliminate
any possible free choice for “essentially private reasons” for
them.
The more soldiers
respond to a desire to serve a common cause, Walzer charges, “the more likely
we are to regard it as a crime to force him to fight. We assume that his
commitment is to the safety of his country, that he fights only when it is
threatened, and that then he has to fight (he has been ‘put to it’): it is his
duty and not a free choice.”[6] Since
states and not soldiers bear the responsibility for decisions to wage war (and
to obtain soldiers to fight those wars), we ought not judge soldiers based on
the wars they fight, as those wars are not theirs. Rather, our judgment
of them must be limited to how they fight. Soldiers and soldiers
who oppose them (the entire suite of combatants in a conflict) are therefore
moral equals, and fully entitled on all sides to warriors’ rights as prescribed
by the rules of war.[7] In
simplified form, the argument runs like this:
________________
The Problem with “Unlawful
Combatants.”
Clearly, Walzer’s argument
eliminates immediately the type of terrorist who attacks innocents.
Premise 5 evokes the rules of war as an initial sorting device, and it seems
fair to say that soldiers of Al Qaeda who hijack planes, blow themselves up in crowded
marketplaces, and perpetrate other similar acts of violence against innocents
obviously break the rules of war, and thus forfeit their status and rights as
legitimate combatants. There is no moral obligation to offer benevolent
quarantine to suicide terrorists, as they obviate their moral equality as
combatants by targeting the very people that legitimate combatants are morally
charged to protect.
The tougher
question, though, is how Al Qaeda foot soldiers figure in to this moral
calculus. The
Though not clearly
articulated by U.S. authorities, one might argue that the moral basis for the
legal minuet described above might be roughly stated this way: these soldiers,
though they fought conventionally and in accordance with the rules of war, are
ultimately aligned with an illegitimate and inherently evil cause that seeks
the intentional murder of innocents to further its goals. This means that
when they resist apprehension by force, they are murderers when they kill our
soldiers. This very obviously makes them the wholesale “enemies of
civilization,”[11]
and the worst sort of criminals. In short, they are “bad guys” who need
to be locked up and the keys thrown away. Granting them rights runs the
risk of granting them some degree of ability to continue to wreak havoc against
the peaceful world.
The allegation
about the legitimacy of Terrorism as a sponsoring entity for soldiers is an
important point, though one for which a thorough discussion appeals more
directly to the jus ad bellum dimension of Just War Theory, and is
beyond the scope of this paper. A comment worth mentioning, however, is that
any questions leveled at the notion of Terrorism being a “state-like” entity
must also call into question the ability of “real” states to declare and wage
war (in the fullest sense of the term) on such more closely resemble criminal
conglomerations, and are more appropriately addressed from within the
boundaries of traditional law enforcement. Or, to borrow a
The argument I
want to advance here rather centers on the problem that the
Judging these
soldiers inside a larger judgment about the justness of their cause clearly
violates Just War Theory’s prescription against the requirement for jus ad
bellum/jus in
…the moral status of individual soldiers on both sides is
very much the same: they are led to fight by their loyalty
to their own states and by their lawful obedience. They
are most likely to believe that their wars are just, and while
the basis of that belief in not necessarily rational inquiry
but, more often, a kind of unquestioning acceptance of
official propaganda, nevertheless they are not criminals;
they face each other as moral equals. [13]
Opposing soldiers
have every right to want to kill their opponents, and cannot be called
murderers provided that in doing so they, as Walzer terms it, “fight well,” or
abide by the rules of war. It is after all a common task of all
soldiers—to defeat, and if necessary as part of that process, kill the soldiers
from the force that opposes them. To deny this based on a subjective
assessment of the cause of those soldiers’ war—a cause that they do not
choose—is to deny them the very role that they are called—and in most cases
coerced—to fill.
The notion of
coercion is important in formulating a Walzerian objection to current
Other, more
troubling reasons could include the fact that these soldiers could be
assembling on the battlefield to escape a bullet to their heads if they
resist—or to enable their families to escape a similar fate. Finally, the
promise of payment in hard currency is compelling to many as a means to escape
the desperate living conditions of places like Afghanistan. Some who
are emboldened by the promise of money are mercenaries outright, arriving from
other war-torn regions like Chechnya as experienced guns for hire for an
organization willing to pay good money for experienced soldiers. Even
these ought to be considered carefully, as arguably their ranks are filled
“from among desperate and impoverished men,” whose reasons for fighting are
perhaps not as stark, but most probably still stem from the coercive conditions
of despair, poverty, and hopelessness that undeniably spawn in places like
Chechnya. What is clear about all of these factors—religious
idealism, despair, patriotic duty, poverty, and others—constitute coercive
forces on Walzer’s account. Collectively, these particular Al Qaeda foot
soldiers don’t in fact choose for “essentially private reasons” to take up arms
against the western forces arriving in their lands; rather, they do so because
they feel they must do so. Provided they follow the rules of war, the war
they fight is not their war, and judgment about them must incorporate this to
be right.
While the truth
about the evil of Terrorism is an obvious one, judgments that attempt to paste
it onto the actions of rule-following enemy soldiers wrongly blur the jus ad
bellum/jus in bello distinction that Just War Theory mandates, and perhaps
just as bad, do much to fuel the allegations of U.S. adversaries about the
reality of American-style victors’ justice. If Walzer notions about the
moral equality of soldiers are right, soldiers—even those rallying under the
dubious guidon of “terrorism”—who fight justly deserve just treatment, even if
such treatment dampens intelligence-gathering efforts and seems politically
precarious. Clearly, upholding a reverence for the innate value of human
rights in the most trying of times is a moral mandate for nations like America
who weave such imperatives into the very fabric of their national being.
Works
Cited
Arena,
Kelli. “Lawyer: Dirty Bomb Suspect’s Rights Violated.” CNN.com
[newsonline];
Available
from http://www.cnn.com/2002/US/06/11/dirty.bomb.suspect.
Internet.
Accessed 27 January 2003.
Bush, George W. The National Security Strategy of the
United States. In “Full Text:
Bush’s National Security Strategy,” New York Times [news online];
Available
from
http://www.nytimes.com/2002/09/20/politics/20STEXT_FULL.html.
Internet. Accessed 20 November
2002.
Cohen, Andrew. “ ’Enemy Combatant’ in Legal Limbo.”
CBSNEWS.com Court Watch
[news online]; Available from
http://www.cbsnews.com/stories/2002/06/21/news/opinion/courtwatch/main5130
87.shtml. Internet. Accessed 27 January 2003.
“Diluting the Geneva Convention,” New York Times, June
21 2002.
Luban, David. “The War on Terrorism and the End of Human
Rights.” In Philosophy
and Public Policy Quarterly, Volume 22, No. 3, Summer 2002
.
Walzer, Michael. Just and Unjust Wars: A Moral Argument
with Historical Illustrations,
3rd Ed. (New York: Basic Books, 1977).
NOTES
[1] Kelli Arena,
“Lawyer: Dirty Bomb Suspect’s Rights Violated.” CNN.com [news online];
Available from http://www.cnn.com/2002/US/06/11/dirty.bomb.suspect.
Internet. Accessed 27 January 2003. Padilla remains locked up
indefinitely in a Navy brig in South Carolina with no trial date currently
pending.
[2] George W. Bush, The
National Security Strategy of the United States. In “Full Text:
Bush’s National Security Strategy,” New York Times [news online];
Available from
http://www.nytimes.com/2002/09/20/politics/20STEXT_FULL.html.
Internet. Accessed 20 November 2002.
[3] “Diluting the Geneva
Convention,” New York Times, June 21 200 2.
[4] Andrew Cohen, “
’Enemy Combatant’ in Legal Limbo.” CBSNEWS.com Court Watch [news online];
Available from
http://www.cbsnews.com/stories/2002/06/21/news/opinion/courtwatch/main513087.shtml.
Internet. Accessed 27 January 2003.
[5] David Luban,
“The War on Terrorism and the End of Human Rights.” In Philosophy and
Public Policy Quarterly, Volume 22, No. 3, Summer 2002 , 10.
[6] Michael
Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars: A Moral Argument with Historical
Illustrations, 3rd Ed. (New York: Basic Books, 1977), 27.
[7] “Rules of War” is
Walzer’s general reference to the Laws of Armed Conflict, though he includes
and often intends also reference to the moral precepts behind those laws in
addition to the laws themselves. In this case, I specifically intend
warriors’ rights to include provisions in place in the event of capture and/or
imprisonment—what Walzer refers to as “benevolent quarantine.”
[8] Walzer, 27.
[9] Ibid, 127-8
and 138. This is the first tenet of Walzer’s “War Convention,” which
prescribes the moral distinction between combatants and
noncombatants.
[10]
Luban, 10.
[11]
The National Security Strategy of the United States. In
“Full Text: Bush’s National Security Strategy,” New York Times [news
online]; Available from
http://www.nytimes.com/2002/09/20/politics/20STEXT_FULL.html.
Internet. Accessed 20 November 2002.
[12]
Ibid., 12. Luban remarks that calling the U.S. response to 9/11 a
“war” on terrorism obscures further the moral point about captured Al Qaeda
soldiers’ rights. Making it a war enables the sense of urgency and risk
to elevate far beyond that of normal criminal threats, and allows the
authorities at hand to abolish rights with near-impunity.
[13]
Walzer, 127.