“Identity,
Loyalty and Combat Effectiveness:
A
Cautionary Tale”
JSCOPE 2006
Introduction
Dawson: We joined the Marines because we wanted to live
our lives by a certain code, and we found it in the Corps. Now you're asking us
to sign a piece of paper that says we have no honor. You're asking us to say
we're not Marines. If a court decides that what we did was wrong, then I'll
accept whatever punishment they give. But I believe I was right sir, I believe
I did my job, and I will not dishonor myself, my unit, or the Corps so I can go
home in six months... Sir.
In
“A Few Good Men” the character
For the past several decades, military ethicists
and professionals debated which moral theories (Aristotle, Kant or
Utilitarianism) might provide the best foundation for the practice of the
military profession and the conduct of war.
In this paper, I want to take a different direction and examine what
effects ideas of identity – both individual and social – have on ethical
frameworks, unit cohesion and combat effectiveness. I will argue that training of soldiers should
focus not simply on skills and competence (which is not to say that those are
not important), but should also give prominent treatment to strategies that
make links to identity. To provide some foundation for an account, I
will use two core ideas taken from Nietzsche’s discussion of the warrior
archetype (professionalism and internalization), and apply them to the issue of
loyalty – one area where the connections to identity are clear, but also
problematic. Finally, I will make some
suggestions about how military training might need to be changed in order to
accommodate these insights about identity.
I.
In this
first section, I examine some of the literature on the connections between
identity, ethical frameworks and job performance, particularly in the military
context. I believe this literature
highlights the significant role identity plays: it not only affects combat
(job) effectiveness but also moral agency, as well as the connections between
the two.
However,
the term identity is fraught with all kinds of connotations and ideas, so it
will be essential to start with a rough working definition. One (but by no means the only) useful starting
definition is provided by Owen Flanagan who sees identity:
…as constituted by the
dynamic, integrated system of past and present identifications, desires,
commitments, aspirations, beliefs, dispositions, temperament, roles, acts and
actual patterns; as well as whatever self-understanding (even incorrect ones)
that each person brings to his/her own life.[2]
This definition
provides insight into the individual components of identity, but two additional
aspects are needed: first, the importance of the social context, and second,
further emphasis on identity as a critical (as in self-critical) process. With these additional components, ‘identity’
denotes a ‘fulfilled’ or ‘authentic’ identity which it is not simply taken as a
given, static fact about oneself, but the result of a long, dynamic (to borrow
Flanagan’s apt term) and critical process.
Rather than seeing identity as a possession, identity is something one
is in the process of cultivating, leaving open the possibility of changing,
evolving and altering one’s identity in response to either individual or social
influences and concerns (or both.)
The
first major area of research on identity examines how the above elements play
into the question of job performance, which in the military context means
combat effectiveness (since that is usually the central task of the military,
notwithstanding the debate about other roles for the military.) Thomas Britt (1999) found that soldiers were
most likely to be engaged in their jobs when they found the guidelines clear,
felt personal control over job performance and when job was relevant to their
training.[3] Britt and Bliese recently found that job
engagement buffered individuals from the adverse effects of stressful military
operation.[4] Britt also argues that aspects of an
individual’s identity can promote engagement even when the conditions are less
than optimal.
Identity-relevance
has been clearly connected to job performance, dealing with adversity in job
task and persistence in goal attainment.
In one study Britt looked at the group of characteristics he termed
‘warriorism” (the belief that war is
inevitable and expected and/or part of human nature) with the following
question: Did ‘warriorism’ moderate the relationship between conditions of the
work environment and job engagement?
What he found was that the more the soldiers endorsed the value of
‘warriorism’ (as a part of their personal identity) the greater their job
engagement, and the less likely they were to experience problems when the
parameters were unclear. Interestingly,
the endorsement of the ‘peacekeeping’ identity did not seem to decrease job
engagement, which leads Britt to suggest that soldiers could have components of
a ‘warrior’ and ‘peacekeeping’ identity.[5] In addition, strong identity identification
(regardless of whether it was warrior or peacekeeper oriented) promoted job
engagement under adverse conditions, but weak identity had the opposite effect.[6] However, strong peacekeeper identity did not
show the same level of buffering effects that the strong warrior identity did.[7]
In another
study, Volker Franke argues identity is a part of the dynamic network of
central life interests.[8]
In an examination of war crimes by
Canadian peacekeepers in
Identity
negotiation is a tool for resolving these issues with parts of their
self-conceptions (conflicts involving identities), since people tend to avoid
behaving in ways that class with an identity that is central or most central to
their self-conception.[11] The more committed that people are to an
identity, the higher probability of role performance that supports and reinforces
that identity.[12] In the
As a trained warrior, the
soldier may do well in peace enforcement since that does not conflict with any
central life interest, but peacekeeping and peace building may conflict with
the core warrior identity. Britt argued
that events that allow soldiers to recall previous training experiences, rely
on clear mission objectives or unambiguous ROE will make things clear (invoking
the core warrior image during combat), but in the
Another core issue in combat effectiveness in
numerous studies has been found to be unit cohesion – that is the extent to
which a group of soldiers works, thinks and acts in unison, cooperation and
concern for the other members of the group.
Unit cohesion develops, according to one study, in a climate of
integrity, trust and respect across ranks which derive from mutually agreed
upon definitions of proper behavior.[15] In this study,
In numerous
studies of both American Vietnam performance and Israeli performance during the
Arab-Israeli and Lebanon Wars, the evidence indicates that it is leadership and
trust in the leader and one's comrades that makes the difference in combat
effectiveness. What Belenky, Noy and
Solomon (1981) found with Israeli soldiers was that company morale was highly correlated
with personal morale and that high levels of both were correlated with good
combat effectiveness. Personal morale
was most influenced (in order) by trust in company commander, confidence in
personal soldiering skills, feelings about legitimacy of the war, trust in
weapons, trust in self, confidence in comrades, unit cohesiveness and quality
of relationship with command.[16] They also found that trust in the commander
could and did hold a company and their combat effectiveness together, even when
the other factors faltered or were undermined.
This is consistent with Gabriel and Savage (1978) who found that the
principle cause of reduced combat effectiveness in
These studies
which show the intersections between ethical frameworks (especially understood
in terms of leadership), unit cohesion and combat effectiveness highlight the
second major element of the literature on identity: its relationship to moral
conceptions and moral agency. The idea
of identity as a dynamic process with ramifications for moral agency is borne
out by several empirical studies. The first is a study of nurses where it was
found that their identity as nurses was central to their experience of their
own moral agency and ideas of what was ethical.[17] The study highlights how the personal
narrative the nurses used as their vehicle (for discussing the relationship
between identity and morality) reflected general, more universal narratives
appealing to ideas of what an ethical nurse acted like within the culture of
nursing. The fact that the nurses
situated their understanding of their moral agency within the context of the
‘ethical nurse’ confirms that the identity process was socially situated,
constructed and mediated by the culture of nursing and the social influences of
the other members of that community.
This study also demonstrates how in the relationship between identity
and morality there is a yearning for completeness and wholeness. The nurses constructed their narratives to
show how either they were moving toward the ideal of being an ‘ethical nurse’
or by identifying obstacles that were thwarting their movement in that
direction (and then the narrative expressed that frustration and alienation
caused as a result.)
This desire for
authenticity is also confirmed by an empirical study of Holocaust participants
where it was found that the underlying reason for action (or inaction) was not
religion, duty or reason but how the participants saw their own identity in
relation to others.[18] The study concluded that habits of caring for
others became so ingrained, so routinized that it was appropriate to talk of an
altruistic personality tightly connected to the agent’s sense of identity. Consider the case of Le Chambon, a remote French
village that during the Holocaust was responsible for saving the lives of
thousands of children.[19] What is instructive here is the strong sense
of identity and community which appears to be the source of the moral
action. Of particular note is the level
of internalization or naturalness with which the moral response came when the
situation presented itself. ‘What else could we do?’ and ‘How could we refuse?’
were common responses by the villagers when outside commentators extolled their
moral virtue.[20] Clearly the villagers did not see saving
these children as following a rule or upholding an abstract principle, but as
an organic and natural expression of their Huguenot history, their community of
faith and common experiences - as if everything up to that point had prepared
them to inevitably act.
These
studies all reflect the common theme that there is clearly a connection between
self-conceptions and ideas of identity (which includes components of both
individual and group identity) which have ramifications for moral agency as
well as unit cohesion and combat effectiveness.
This highlights an element that the traditional moral theories either
minimize or fail to take into account in their applications to military
ethics. I want to suggest that one can
take the identity of the military professional (which includes both group and
individual aspects) as the foundation or starting point for a moral perspective
for military ethics, rather than something to be taken into account after the
‘correct’ moral perspective is established (only as a matter of application.)
II.
Taking these connections related to identity as a given,
how might they be fleshed out in terms of a theoretical perspective that takes
seriously the role of identity? The
above studies highlight the extent to which individuals experienced congruency
between parts of their self-conception and the roles they were being asked to
play in their job, profession or vocation.
It is this congruency, moral authenticity, lack of moral pretense, which
Nietzsche finds so attractive and noteworthy in what he terms the warrior/noble
type. In this section I will give a
brief sketch of the warrior/noble archetype in Nietzsche and highlight two
elements that can serve for a broader identity based moral perspective.
Alongside his
critique of the ‘slave morality’ and his praise of the Dionysian artist,
Nietzsche’s admiration for the warrior is one of the most consistent themes
across his work.[21] Nietzsche sees this archetype as embodying
many of his keys ideas about freedom, the ‘will to power’ and affirmation of
the natural life. Nietzsche begins with
the savageness of man. “…so much fear remains, so much superstitious fear of the ‘savage cruel beast’ whose conquest is
the very pride of these more humane ages, that even palpable truths remain
unspoken for centuries…because they look as if they might reanimate that savage
beast one has finally ‘mortified.’[22]
We need not fear loosening the savage beast, according to Nietzsche, because
its ‘domestication’ is only an illusion and it lurks very nearby. Rather it should be pressed into service (as
the warrior/noble type) not ignored nor repressed.
Second, the
warrior archetype reflects the (revised) Dionysian idea of controlled
passion. In On the Genealogy of
Morals, Nietzsche traces the history of the word 'good,' claiming that the
Latin bonus can be traced to back to an earlier duonus which
meant solider or warrior. Consequently, bonus
became the man of strife and dissension, the man of war, which Nietzsche takes
to demonstrate what constituted goodness of a man in ancient
Refraining from injury,
violence and exploitation and placing one’s will on a par with someone else’s,
this may become good manners among individuals if the appropriate conditions
are present (namely, if these men are actually similar in strength and value
standards and belong together in one body.)
But as soon as this principle is extended, and possibly even accepted as
the fundamental principle of society, it immediately proves to be what
it really is - a will to the denial of life, a principle of
disintegration and decay.[24]
Third, Nietzsche highlights a kind of instinct and
reverence for rank as a crucial characteristic, "...There is an instinct
for rank, which...is the sign of high rank; there is a delight in
the nuances of reverence that allows us to infer noble origin and habits....
Anyone to whose task and practice it belongs to search out souls...he will test
it for its instinct of reverence."[25] For
Nietzsche this understanding of rank is not simply about external titles,
positions and signs. Rather, it is about
a more internal self-understanding and way of being that sees the exchange of
certain rights, duties and honors as part of the natural order of things, not
as something imposed by rule of law.
Nietzsche continues by citing what he sees as other signs of nobility,
"...never thinking of degrading our duties into duties for everybody; not
wanting to delegate, to share one's own responsibility; counting one's
privileges and their exercise among one's duties."
Fourth, Nietzsche's warrior archetype maintains the life
affirming 'will to power' and strength of the savage beast, but is also one who
belongs to a strict sort of 'brotherhood,' where there are complex rules and
traditions that apply to the members and are not intended to apply outside it.[26]
To be incapable of
taking one's enemies, one's accidents, even one's misdeeds seriously for very
long -- that is the sign of strong, full natures in whom there is an excess of
the power to form, to mold, to recuperate and to forget .... Such a man shakes
off with a single shrug many vermin that eat deep into others; here
alone is genuine 'love of one's enemies' is possible..... How much reverence
has the noble man for his enemies! -- and such reverence is a bridge to
love. For he desires his enemy for
himself, as his mark of distinction; he can endure no other enemy than the one
in whom there is nothing to despise and very much to honor![27]
Nietzsche adheres
to a remarkably conservative (and some would say outmoded) view of war: combat
between equals is war, an art, a vocation to be practiced by inducted members;
combat among non-equals is a massacre with no honor or nobility involved –
killing for its own sake. This is an
important distinction in Nietzsche's argument that war and the warrior are
valuable and life affirming. It is not
the killing, maiming and terror that are themselves valuable, but within
specific contexts they can be a means
to creativity, life affirmation and value.
What conclusions can be drawn from this praise of the
warrior archetype? First, Nietzsche’s
focus on the warrior archetype reveals the larger importance of the
relationship between a moral perspective and the identity (either individual or
communal, or both) out of which that moral perspective arises. The sense of ‘vocation’ that the warrior has
gives rise to the moral requirements of that vocation, and this sense of moral
commitment reinforces his sense of himself as a warrior.[28] This unique vocation (just as the nurses in
the study cited above) is also pursued in a unique community (even in
democratic societies - we do not all suit up and wage war, we have
professionals to do it on our behalf) which will also generate a group
identity, and in turn and internal group morality which serves to reinforce
that identity. This sense of
“professionalism” is the starting point for Nietzsche’s warrior to reflect on
what is means to be noble; a similar sense of “professionalism” might spur a
businessperson to reflect on what it means to be ethical in the practice of
business.
Second,
Nietzsche’s sense of the noble (the distinguishing trait of the warrior)
depends on the fact that the other members of the group have internalized and
are seriously committed to these values and will therefore uphold and enforce
them as a part of their own identities. Part of the reason these values are so
effective lies in the moral commitment borne by the other members of the group
and the possibility of expulsion from the group (or other sanction) if the
standards are not upheld. The same could
be seen to apply on the individual level; compromising one’s moral standards is
not just about breaking a rule or violating a principle (as we see also in the
empirical studies highlighted above), but involves betraying part of one’s
identity, failing one’s own sense of self.
Both
of these ideas are crucial in establishing a moral perspective grounded in
identity for two reasons. First, they
take seriously the idea that the identity is the starting point for the moral
perspective, which arises out of both the sense of group and individual
identities. Second, they do not simply
take the identity (identities) as unreflectively given, but provide a mechanism
for a dynamic process of change and evolution – including the possibility (which is not the same as likelihood) of critique and reevaluation
of the foundations and elements of the identity. What is means to be a professional and what
values are important to be internalized is a matter of community and individual
consideration; it would be odd if there were not challenges to and critical
discussions of these elements (with possible revisions and/or new
understandings) over time.
Taking these two key insights from
Nietzsche’s view – professionalism and internalization – we turn to loyalty to
examine the applications of an identity based view. Loyalty is an important virtue in military
communities (both as a part of individual as well as group identities) and will
allow us to see both the advantages of an identity-focused moral perspective,
but also the problems created by and the dangers of identity.
What does loyalty mean in the
military community? A good place to
start is The Soldiers Guide (FM 21-13), which is designed to orient the
new recruit to the military community and begin to foster the military ethos.
To be a good leader and a good soldier, you must be
loyal. Stand by your organization and the
officers, non-commissioned officers, and fellow soldiers in it....The habits of
obedience....are a necessary part of Army life.
Obey
promptly and cheerfully the orders given to you. Obedience and teamwork will make your
performance better and your fellow soldier's tasks easier.[29]
In
combat, the success of the mission and the lives of fellow soldiers and herself
may well depend upon obedience. However,
it is not simply a matter of blindly, unreflectively doing what one is told; a good soldier needs to develop a sense of duty
which can help her ascertain what she should be doing, she cannot simply do as
told. The best soldiers are ones that
can be given a task with very little direction.
They know what is required and have a guidance system of sorts,
reflecting Nietzsche’s idea internalization, which allows them to carry out the
order in the most efficient, correct or consistent way
The second pillar of loyalty in the
military ethos is teamwork, esprit de
corps or unit cohesion (as discussed in the studies above). The soldier owes loyalty to his superiors,
but he also owes his loyalty to the members of his unit, to his fellow
soldiers. When asked what helped them
when the going got rough, the overwhelming answer cited by the guide (as well
as numerous psychological studies) is that they 'didn't want to let the other
men down.'[30]
The guide goes onto stress this critical aspect of military life:
...you
find yourself part of a team, and you will be expected to play your part in
it. This is not all give and no take,
for while you are giving strength to your outfit, it will be giving strength
right back to you. The more you put in,
the more you will get out. This is one of the most important facts of
Army life and one of the hardest to put into words.[31]
The
unit (or other primary group) comes to have an identity of its own with its own
traditions, customs and history into which the new members must be inculcated
and which they are expected to support and draw upon for support. In addition to being a member of a unit, the
soldier is part of the larger military community. We can see how these two pillars of loyalty
come together in the oath, Code of Conduct and Soldiers Creed. First, the Oath (either the commissioning
oath or another oath of office given at induction ceremonies) makes clear to
the soldier that his life has changed and that he has taken up a new position
and way of life. Upon taking the oath,
the soldier enters into a new moral, legal and social situation with its own
rules, traditions and norms; it is an entirely new way of life and central to
it is obedience to leaders and respect for the bonds with other soldiers. Consider the Soldier's Creed:
I
am proud of my own organization. I will
do all I can to make it the finest unity of the Army. I will be loyal to those under whom I serve. I will do my full part to carry out ordered
and instructions given me or my unit....No matter what situation I am in, I
will never do anything, for pleasure, profit, or personal safety, which will disgrace
my uniform, my unit or my country. I will
use every means I have, even beyond the line of duty, to restrain my Army comrades
from actions disgraceful to themselves and the uniform.[32]
This
statement makes it evident that the soldier is obligated to follow orders given
by superiors, but is also obligated to a certain understanding of the military
community. This understanding is stated
in the strongest moral terms of refraining from doing anything to disgrace
uniform, unit or country, all symbolic representations of the ideals and values
of the military community. To do harm to
anyone of them is to harm not just the honor of the individual soldier, but the
unit, Army and nation that he represents.
All of these are now part of his identity, not external considerations
(as they might have been before.)
With a better understanding of why
loyalty is so important and valued in the military context, we turn to Michael Wheeler's account of
loyalty, which gives us a good way to conceptualize the idea of loyalty. In his essay "Loyalty, Honor and the
Modern Military," Wheeler argues that for loyalty to be effective and
meaningful in the long run, it must be inspired by trust and not fear.[33] Without
trust a person may be able to momentarily compel compliance to orders or
wishes, but this compliance is not the same as loyalty. This is borne out by Army Field Manual 22-100:
the essence of leadership is to get the men to do what one wants them to do
voluntarily, without having to resort to force or threats. In other words, get them to want to do it.[34] The idea is that if the men trust their
commander, they will be loyal. Why? Trust generates sentiments of pleasure,
sympathy, empathy, affection etc. which predispose us to take the leader's
sentiments, desires, aims etc. as our own.
When that happens, there is a motivation for acting that, unlike fear,
can remain potent even when the commander is not watching every move of the
soldier.
If loyalty is generated by trust,
how then do we come to trust someone?
Wheeler argues that trust is usually given if we perceive integrity in
the object of trust. Wheeler
acknowledges critique and questioning can be an important part of loyalty, but
insists that agents respond to integrity in their leaders and this is what
inspires loyalty. This happens because
we, as agents, reflect upon the integrity of the person before us and our
recognition of the importance and value, both to ourselves and others, of this
integrity generates a certain positive sentiment: trust. This trust is absolutely crucial to notions
of loyalty, as well as other military character traits, because "...This
trust can serve to close the gap between the values of the soldier and his
commander, for trust creates a sympathetic attitude and propensity to
obey."[35]
We can see that both the military’s
own expressions about loyalty, as well as Wheeler’s more philosophical analysis
of the ideas reflect many of the connections discussed both in the empirical
literature and Nietzsche’s insights on the warrior archetype. Loyalty becomes the mark of the professional,
as well as a crucial virtue (with many different and sometimes competing
aspects) that must be internalized if one is going to be a member of the
group. We also see the connections
discussed above in
But what about the negative side of
loyalty? Consider the following:
‘Sassaman
decided that throwing the Iraqis into the
In
examining the role of military culture in the Canadian deployment in
In taking the Oath of Service, each
soldier swears allegiance to something larger than the self.[38]
This is “the first step in ethical socialization to the in-group – bringing the
new recruit into a body of individuals drawn together by a common purpose and
thus, a common bond subordinating individualism to group identity.” This socialization is also a crucial part of
basic training in which individual loyalties and preferences need to be broken
down and reformed in favor of group cooperation and loyalty. The importance of unit cohesion to combat
effectiveness has already been emphasized; this socialization is crucial to
building these bonds.
Brotz and Wilson (1946) argued that
bonding was so strong that covering up for, defense of and devotion to one’s
buddy was expected. This can lead to
stonewalling and covering up or preventing individuals from speaking out about
inappropriate behavior. “…If he [the
group leader] incites his group to racist behavior they’ll follow, even if they
don’t agree, because they won’t distinguish themselves from the group. Because the group is all you’ve got. If you’re in battle, no one else is looking
out for you….”[39] By participation in hazing rituals that seem
extreme and even cruel to outsiders, the soldiers are proving their readiness
to participate in the group regardless of person cost, thus gaining group
acceptance.[40]
Another dynamic within the Canadian
Airborne Regiment was the shared sense of elitism, that they were a cut above
the ordinary infantry soldier and that the other soldiers were inferior. This leads to a dynamic of protecting one’s
own against the military hierarchy, as well as against demands or investigations
by civilian authorities, which was noted in the quote from Colonel Sassaman
above. In addition to this problem,
there are concerns about the level of trust (or lack of it) between the junior
and senior officer corps, such as those raised by Snyder and Watkins.[41] The senior officers may be perceived as
having more loyalty to the institutional values and not enough loyalty to the
people involved, while the junior officers may be perceived as being loyal to
their primary group at the expense of the larger institutional concerns and
values. Of particular importance here is
the role of the junior NCO’s, since they link the formal demands and values of
the larger organization to the norms and sanctions of the primary group. One needs close supervision by senior NCO’s
and officers to ensure these connections between the primary group and the
larger organization are preserved in the appropriate way.[42] The issues raised by the prison abuses at Abu
Gharib showed the working of group loyalty without loyalty to the larger values
and institution and the consequences of such loyalties.
In the Canadian case, bad behavior (black
marketeering, drinking) was not reported up the chain of command, so as not to
humiliate the Regiment (the primary group).[43] Whistle blowing is perceived as an instance
of disloyalty, as going against the corporate nature of the military,
especially if it involves whistle blowing to outsiders (i.e. civilian
authorities.) This sense was especially heightened
in peacekeeping missions where the soldiers were in foreign lands where the
primary group bonding is especially intense, since they are the only extended
family that is accessible and immediate. One serious danger in the above is the
view that bad behavior is unofficially tolerated, even if there is not official
approval.[44] Abu Gharib and
The Canadian forces had a tradition of strong unit
cohesion, teamwork and loyalty as part of their group identity and their actions
reflected the desire to preserve this.
This dynamic is surely not a unique one in military culture, and
therefore highlights the dangers of loyalty. If individuals will preserve their
participation or connection to the group identity since it is so connected to
their own self-perceptions, what is to be done in terms of training and moral
education to deal with this dynamic while not sacrificing the benefits of an
identity oriented view?
Given
the importance of identity to combat effectiveness and military culture, but
also considering the dangers of such connections (especially given our above
discussion of loyalty), what can be suggested in terms of training and moral
education? In this section, I want to
offer a cautionary tale and some thumbnail suggestions about how to deal with
these issues. There are two core issues
I will address: first, dealing with the challenges of multiple identity
frameworks; second, training that addresses loyalty to more than just the
primary combat group.
According
to
The
same, of course, applies with regard to the individual soldier. Military historian Alan Millett: notes “The officer’s
identity is partly inherited, partly self-developed. He inherits the broadly
defined characteristics of his career and the special institutional setting
within which he finds himself. He must
develop stable and lasting concepts of self that are compatible with his
profession. This transformation or
‘professional socialization’ is not taken lightly by the other practioners with
whom he begins his career.”[46] While in the past, notions of professionalism
tended to be oriented around the warrior model (as reflected by the primary
orientation of the military as large-scale combat), it seems that contemporary
soldiers have at least three major roles or identities with which they wrestle
and among which they must be able to effectively navigate – 1) warrior (combat);
2) peacekeeper/police functions (even in domestic situations) and 3) peacemaking/humanitarian
roles.
Franke
argues for an integration of the warrior and peacekeeping identities: “…soldiers
and officers who view war fighting and peacekeeping as equally important
components of their central life interests will more easily be able to switch
among mission requirements without jeopardizing their self conceptions.”[47] He also encourages training that requires
negotiation between multiple identities; facing these kinds of identity
dilemmas for the first time in the field is not a good thing since it limits
behavioral choices (denial, bolstering strategies, not wanting to let the group
down). Therefore, the military needs a
new identity with both combat and non-combat identity components. In other words, soldiers must be able to
embrace multiple identities and practice integration and negotiation between
them before they get out there in the field.
I would argue that it is essential for
training of soldiers not simply focus on the traditional warrior role, but also
develop a robust sense of the other roles that soldiers will have to carry out as a integral part of who and what they are
as soldiers, not as add-on tasks that there is no one else to do. The add-on
attitude is entirely understandable, but also dangerous. If these other roles are not seen as an
integral part of the soldier identity, they will be jettisoned at the first
sign of conflict or adversity. If
soldiers are used to (via role playing, regular case studies and informal
discussion) to moving between the different roles, then this skill at
negotiation and navigation between multiple frameworks will become internalized
and therefore, itself a part of the soldier’s (and institution’s) identity. If soldiers are not used to navigating and
living in multiple frameworks ( as the case of
Even if
soldiers are able to effectively embrace and negotiate multiple identities, the
dark side of an identity-oriented perspective must be addressed.
We also
need to understand the dynamics of atrocities and war crimes. Having once done something bad they can be
offered an escape from guilt by praise or membership in a prestigious group but
this only works for a short time. In the
long term it requires that the soldiers continue to validate their initial atrocity
by performing more and by participating in rituals (with the group) of
justification since they are dependent on one another for mutual validation.[50]
We see numerous examples of this point
in the literature on gang warfare and child soldiers where committing violent,
atrocious acts is seen as a way to bond the individual continually to the group
(and so such actions must be regularized) as well as isolating the individuals
from prior moral, social, religious or familial support networks and
identities.
Snyder
and Watkins point out several problems with Army professionalism within the
Institution (as opposed to an attribute of particular soldiers) as one source
of difficulty. First, they see a lack of
connection (increasingly) between the Army’s notion of professionalism and the
personal self-conceptions of the soldiers and insist on a need for better
integration between these.[51]
Second, there is an inability to control unprofessional behavior at top levels
which is fueling distrust especially between the higher and lower officer corps
groups. This dynamic seems to me to be
the more serious of the two issues when it comes to the role that primary group
loyalty plays in war crimes and other unethical (or illegal) behavior; we see
it clearly operating in Vietnam, the Somalia case cited above as well as in Abu
Gharib.
What is
to be done about these problems? What
are some specific strategies in training and education what would address these
issues? Winslow argues that discipline
and leadership can do much to offset excessive group identification and the
issues that come with it. A unit with a
strong sense of professionalism as part of their group identity would be able
to avoid and deal with infractions because individuals are then invested in an
identity which has components of self-discipline and ethics (even at personal
cost) embedded in it. These need to be
continually reinforced by leadership at all times and in all situations.[52]
I would
agree with this by a reminder that for Nietzsche both professionalism and
internalization of community values are central for the warrior archetype. Both of these elements must include
components that relate to multiple roles, but also include the values not just
of the primary group, but also the larger institution and the society which it
serves. This is the difficult task. It is not hard, as we have seen, to inculcate
individuals into the values of the primary group, but it can be challenging to
provide the same kind of internalization when it comes to the values of an
institution or a larger social group – especially if the members of the primary
group regard those values as inferior or contrary to their own.[53]
Soldiers must be given opportunities to
bond with and practice the values of the larger institution and society in a
similar way as they are given these opportunities with the primary group
members. Training and education must not
just take into account one aspect of the soldier’s identity, but also many
aspects as possible so that the soldier sees these aspects as integrated (or at
least that they can be integrated) and internalizes the ability and confidence
to maneuver between them (reducing the adverse power of the group identity.)
Conclusion
I have tried to
make the case here that an identity based perspective on military ethics is a
symbiotic, mutually reinforcing relation which leaves open a great deal of room
for internal and external critique, questioning and accountability, but still
takes seriously the idea that the ethical life of the warrior, the physician
and the businessperson are neither interchangeable nor reducible to one
another. One must start with both the
group and individual elements of the military identity (or identities) and use
those elements and insights to produce ethical frameworks and perspectives,
rather than trying to take a general ethical framework as given and then look
at how it applied to the military profession.
Such an approach opens the bridge between ethical reflection and the
demands of the professions – providing common ground for both theory and identity.
NOTES:
[1] A Few
Good Men (1992)
[2] Quoted
in Michele Mangini, “Character and Well-Being: Towards an Ethics of Character” Philosophy and Social Criticism Vol 26,
Issue 2 (March 2001), p. 80.
[3] Thomas
Britt, “Aspects of Identity Predict Engagement in Work Under Adverse
Conditions” Self and Identity Volume 2 (2003), p. 32
[4] Ibid., p. 33.
[5] Ibid., p. 37-8.
[6] Ibid., p. 39-40.
[7] Ibid.
[8] Volker C. Franke, “Resolving Identity Tensions: The Case of the Peacekeeper” Volume XIX No. 2, Fall 1999, p. 6.
[9] Ibid., p. 1.
[10] Ibid., see Franke’s notes 4 and 5 for further elaboration.
[11] Ibid., p. 4.
[12] Ibid., p 4 see note 26.
[13] Ibid., p. 4 see notes 23 and 24.
[14] Ibid., p. 7 see notes 41-46.
[15] Faris
R. Kirkland PhD, “Honor, Combat Ethics and Military Culture” in Military
Medical Ethics Volume 1, p. 159.
[16]Gregory
Belenky, Shabtai Noy and Zahava Solomon, "
[17] Gweneth
A. Hartrick Doane, “Am I Still Ethical? The Socially-Mediated Process of Nurses
Morality Identity” Nursing Ethics 9 (6) 2002, p. 626.
[18] Kristen
Renwick Monroe, “Morality and a Sense of Self: The Importance of Identity and
Categorization for Moral Action,” American
Journal of Political Science Vol 45, Issue 3 (July 2001), p. 491.
[19] For a
fuller account see Phillip Hallie, Lest Innocent Blood Be Shed.
[20]
[21] For the
critique of the ‘slave morality’ see On the Genealogy of Morals
(specifically the First Essay) and Beyond Good and Evil. For his discussion of Dionysian and Appollian
models of the artist, see The Birth of Tragedy.
[22]
Fredrich Nietzsche, Basic Writings of Nietzsche, ed. Walter Kauffman, Beyond
Good and Evil. (New York: Random
House, 1968), p. 348.
[23] Fredrich Nietzsche, Basic Writings of Nietzsche, ed. Walter Kauffman, On the Genealogy of Morals. (New York: Random House, 1968), p. 467.
[24] Fredrich Nietzsche, Basic Writings of Nietzsche, ed. Walter Kauffman, Beyond Good and Evil. (New York: Random House, 1968), p. 393.
[25] Ibid, p. 402.
[27] Fredrich Nietzsche, Basic Writings of Nietzsche, ed. Walter Kauffman On the Genealogy of Morals. (New York: Random House, 1968), p. 475.
[28] Nietzsche always talks about the warrior/noble in terms of a male archetype and so I maintain this consistency to be true to what Nietzsche has in mind, but I do not necessary agree that this archetype must be male only. However, a sustained discussion of this issue is outside the scope of this paper.
[29]US Army, The Soldier's Guide (Washington D.C.: Department of the Army, 1961), p. 9.
[30]US Army, The Soldier's Guide (Washington D.C.: Department of the Army, 1961), pp. 48, 79. See also Richard A. Gabriel and Paul L. Savage, Crisis in Command, (New York: Hill and Wang, 1978), pp. 8, 94.
[31]US Army, The Soldier's Guide (Washington D.C.: Department of the Army, 1961), p. 48.
[32]US Army, The Soldier's Guide (Washington D.C.: Department of the Army, 1961), pp. 125-6. See also Sidney Axinn's discussion of this topic in A Moral Military, pp. 48-9.
[33]Michael O. Wheeler, "Loyalty, Honor and the Modern Military" in War, Morality and the Military Profession, ed. Malham M. Wakin (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1986), pp. 171-179.
[34]US Army, Military Leadership FM 22-100, (Washington D.C: Department of the Army, 1973), pp. 1-3, 13-1 through 13-7.
[35]Michael O. Wheeler, "Loyalty, Honor and the Modern Military" in War, Morality and the Military Profession, ed. Malham M. Wakin (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1986), p. 178.
[36] (Dexter Filkins, “What the War Did to Colonel
Sassaman” New York Times Magazine
[37] Donna
Winslow, “ Misplaced Loyalties: The Role of Military Culture in the Breakdown
of Discipline in Two Peace Operations” Journal
of Military and Strategic Studies Volume 6, Issue 3 (2004), p. 2-3.
[38] Ibid., p. 4.
[39] Ibid., p. 5.
[40] Ibid., p. 6.
[41] Don
Snider and Gayle Watkins, “The Future of Army Professionalism: A New for
Renewal and Redefinition” Parameters
Fall 2000, p. 10.
[42] Donna Winslow, “ Misplaced Loyalties: The Role of Military Culture in the Breakdown of Discipline in Two Peace Operations” Journal of Military and Strategic Studies Volume 6, Issue 3 (2004), p. 13-14.
[43] Ibid., p. 11-12.
[44] Ibid., p. 13.
[45] Faris R. Kirkland PhD, “Honor, Combat Ethics and Military Culture” in Military Medical Ethics Volume 1, p. 163.
[46] Don Snider and Gayle Watkins, “The Future of Army Professionalism: A New for Renewal and Redefinition” Parameters Fall 2000, p. 7, see note 31.
[47] Volker C. Franke, “Resolving Identity Tensions: The Case of the Peacekeeper” Volume XIX No. 2, Fall 1999, p. 10.
[48] Faris R. Kirkland PhD, “Honor, Combat Ethics and Military Culture” in Military Medical Ethics Volume 1, p. 161.
[49] I thank Brad Lubken for helping me to see this point.
[50] Faris R. Kirkland PhD, “Honor, Combat Ethics and Military Culture” in Military Medical Ethics Volume 1, p. 174.
[51] Don Snider and Gayle Watkins, “The Future of Army Professionalism: A New for Renewal and Redefinition” Parameters Fall 2000, p.6.
[52] Donna Winslow, “ Misplaced Loyalties: The Role of Military Culture in the Breakdown of Discipline in Two Peace Operations” Journal of Military and Strategic Studies Volume 6, Issue 3 (2004), p. 14.
[53] This is one of the serious dangers posed by a military-civilian culture gap, which I have discussed elsewhere.