Pragmatism and Preemption:
Why Just War Theory Isn’t the Law, But It’s Still a Good Idea
Presented to the Joint Services
Conference on Professional Ethics, 27-28 January 2005
By Adam Weinstein, Department of
English,
Abstract
One
perpetual problem with just war theories is the abuse of their most critical
terms as rationalizations for every color of action in the spectrum of human
behavior. Nowhere is this more evident than in the doctrine of preemptive
action; Hitler, Stalin, and Milosevic, among others, have all used the familiar
moral rhetoric of “self-defense” in different ways to undertake “preemptive”
actions against perceived enemies -- actions that are generally seen today as
unjust. If the language of virtue in just war theory is so malleable that it
can be used to cover any vice, is it really of any use to us at all?
The answer
is a qualified yes. If we take the primary goal of a just war theory to be
usefulness in normalizing behavior among nations (rather than correspondence to
a true or universal moral code), then just war theories in general are possible
- but only in a historically contingent sense. I suggest a form for such a
theory, based upon pragmatist “foundations”. Philosophical pragmatists are
primarily concerned with the usefulness (as opposed to the objective truth) of
moral propositions, and they will naturally look toward popular global
consensus – its basis, its composition, and the prospects for directing it - as
a key criterion for the usefulness of a war convention. Consequently,
preemption - and virtually any other type of combat seen today - can be seen as
legitimate, if the threat it addresses is widely and strongly perceived
to exist and if the response is considered proportional to the threat.
I. In his
classic, Just and Unjust Wars, Michael Walzer (1977, 226) recounts an
anecdote about an ancient Chinese general named Duke Hsiang. The Duke was
preparing his army for combat against a superior force from the rival
President
George W. Bush might not rush to embrace parallels between his political
thought and that of the father of Chinese communism, but there are striking
similarities in their policies on military preemption. In pressing for the
invasion of
In abandoning the niceties of diplomacy and deliberation, the
Bush and Mao doctrines highlight, perhaps unconsciously, a serious weakness of
just war theory: the bleak fact that justice is what states make of it. Ask a
White House spokesperson, and you will probably hear that the war in
Some
observers might see progress in the fact that these peoples employ a common
vocabulary of global morality and justice. But what is the point of moral
rhetoric if its terms can be used and abused to allow or condemn virtually any
act? One man’s terrorist is still another man’s freedom fighter, and one
state’s just intervention is still another’s naked aggression. Just war theory,
it seems nowadays, is less a rational tool for the moral evaluation of actions
and more a catch-all rationalization for anything anyone seeks to do.
Central to
this problem of justification is the fact that just war theorists have historically
sought an indisputable metaphysical basis for the rightness and wrongness of
the acts they address. From Augustine, Aquinas, and Grotius to Kant, Webster,
and Wilson, these ambitious thinkers based their views of war upon the
presumption of a timeless, objective morality -- whether it was provided by
God, natural law, or right reason. Even recent liberal theorists place an undue
faith in the power of reason or common sense to provide a shared moral code for
all states and peoples. John Stuart Mill (1963, 377) sought “a definite and
rational test” for “the justifiableness of intervening in the affairs of other
countries.” Peter Singer (2004, 144) asserted that “it is our capacity to
reason that is the universal solvent.” And Michael Walzer (1977, 107) based his
war convention upon “the moral convictions of ordinary men and women,” presuming
a baseline human conscience that has been more conspicuous in its absence than
its abundance in the 20th and 21st centuries. Even if such a global
conscience could be said to exist, at various times it was unmoved by horrors
such as slavery, racism, and imperialism but was shocked by minority education,
free speech, free religion, the heliocentric theory of the universe, and many
other features of the modern world that we accept or tolerate.
The point is
that, no matter which theorist we side with, no matter what basis we maintain
as the real, true source of moral justification, we are inviting
more controversies than we solve and alienating just as many parties as we
satisfy. Yet most justice theorists respond that if we abandon this
philosophical search for timeless truth, we will collapse into the Hobbesian
state of “war of all against all,” a desperate situation of relativism and
wanton violence in which states will do what they must to survive,
justification be damned. As one philosopher states, “unless the modern
experience is to dissolve in the light of the one irresistible,
all-encompassing Good, our political future will be one ‘where ignorant armies
clash by night’” (Larmore 1996, 151).
It is
possible, however, that the choice between asinine ethics and amoral
opportunism is a false dichotomy, a dramatization that results when just war
theorists and political realists talk at or past each other. Between those two
poles lies a gulf of theory and strategy that is largely unexplored. One fresh alternative
is based upon the pragmatist tradition in American philosophy, which supposes
that justice is possible, not as a turn towards some historically unchanging
notion of truth, but as a turn towards an ever-shifting popular consensus. This
consensus would have to be carved out of an ongoing dialogue, an argument that
meets diverse cultures, faiths, beliefs, and prejudices on their own terms,
without reference to an “objective” authority like reason or scripture.
A pragmatist
approach to justification should not be such a shocking turn for statesmen and
soldiers; other experts in persuasion - namely, commercial advertisers - have
for decades assumed that “truth is irrelevant. What matters are the perceptions
that exist in the mind,” no matter, one might add, how absurd, immoral, or
offensive such perceptions may be to the seller. Instead of directly
challenging a targeted population’s perceptions, states one marketer, the
essence of successful product positioning is to accept those
“perceptions as reality and then restructure those perceptions to create the
position you desire” (Ries and Trout 2000, xx).
On this
basis, it is possible to position political and moral norms like any other
market product. Recent philosophical and legal pragmatists believe that
personal and professional values, intuitions, opinions, and so-called common
sense “can sometimes be educated by immersion in ‘the facts,’ if by ‘facts’ we
mean the myriad lessons of our experiences and interactions with our social and
natural environments” (Posner 2002, viii). Hence, by discarding notions of a
distinction between justification and truth – indeed, by claiming that there is
no truth, independent of what we generally accept as true -- we can achieve
moral progress by concentrating on achieving better justificatory ability:
Better
to deal with doubts about what we are saying, either by shoring up what we have
previously said or by saying something different. The trouble with aiming at
truth is that you would not know when you had reached truth, even if you had
reached it. But you can aim at ever more justification, the assuagement of ever
more doubt (Rorty 1999, 82).
On this view, pragmatism replaces a traditional aim of moral
philosophy - the search for objectivity - with the slightly less formidable
task of “getting as much intersubjective agreement as you can manage” (Rorty
1999, 15).
All this is
well and good, but just what can a pragmatist say concretely about
international affairs and war in particular? Implicit in the pragmatist experiment
is the premise that, since no vocabulary is a true representation of nature,
there is no single golden path to securing consensual justice. But, “even if
there is no Way the World Is, even if there is no such thing as ‘the intrinsic
nature of reality,’ there are still causal pressures. These pressures will be
described in different way at different times and for different purposes, but
they are pressures nonetheless” (Rorty 1999, 33). Given a particular account of
our current historical circumstances and their attendant “causal pressures,” I
favor a particular path to cooperation, one in which the onus is on the
so-called “lone superpower” to affirm, honor, and encourage participation in a
new war convention. In such a convention, preemption is permitted – but only if
the world’s lone superpower agrees to assess threats and preemptive measures in
novel ways.
II. From a
pragmatist perspective, the paramount objective in constructing a global war
convention is not to honor a universal notion of the Right or the Good, but to
honor the long-term interests of one’s most vital community, the community
which provides us with our notions of what is right and good: our nation. National
security policy aims to keep this community and its interests safe from external
threats by the most effective means available. For much of the past century,
the greatest threat to national security was considered to be the possibility
of war between superpowers or other nuclear nations; while this possibility
still exists in limited form, the developed world is now convinced that its top
security priority is to prevent a catastrophic terrorist attack similar to what
occurred on
Such
objectives in a war on terror require us to work for an expansion of the “we”,
as Richard Rorty calls it: the worldwide extension of the group of people who
are more like us than threatening to us. The need to deny
terrorists safe havens for their tactics and their ideologies obliges us to
ensure that the world is peopled with decent societies that hold a nominal
respect for our nation and its objectives.
There are multiple approaches to this
task. The direct approach is to unapologetically claim our own moral sentiments
to be unequaled and to press for their acceptance by a larger community through
any means available, effectively moving to turn the globe into one immense
sphere of American influence. This is the approach generally preferred by the
current administration, and it is tempting to the soldier and statesman alike.
Such a perspective begins from the realist political assumption that security from
terrorists and rogue states is too precious to be entrusted to international
governmental organizations such as the United Nations. The pragmatist
sympathizes with this assumption; the UN is a ponderous, deliberative
bureaucracy carved up into factions, each with its own moral and material
interests, and the limits of its effectiveness are considerable. Better to
entrust one’s security to one’s own armies and politicians. The terrorist
threat, however, is unique in the challenges it poses to national security,
particularly in its talents for concealment and secrecy. Any state or territory
that is an “x factor” in terms of its dedication to American values is a
potential haven for the enemy and must be brought into the camp of allies. The
Bush administration, consequently, derives a very moral conclusion from its
realist assumptions: it sees preemptive action as a right reserved to each
nation for use when necessary, and it justifies that right in terms of (what it
perceives to be) not only American but universal moral values. The safest
world, on this view, is a world that accepts our account of justice; any party
that does not is a rogue and must be persuaded - by force, if necessity
dictates it. As the President stated in his
Political pragmatism earnestly agrees
with the premises of this doctrine: a pragmatist theorist will use
international organizations when possible to further American security
interests, and will abandon them whenever necessary to preserve those
interests. It is in the identification of such “necessities,” however, that
pragmatism departs from the Bush doctrine. Without recourse to absolutes such
as God’s laws or right reason to anchor one’s views of moral action, it is
senseless for the United States to claim an immutable right to preemption
against the rest of the world, unless the rest of the world assents to it – and
if it does not, then it is the United States’ responsibility to abide by that
global consensus, not because it is right
to do so, but because it furthers our long-term interests. Only by meeting
global resistance to our interests halfway can that resistance be overcome. An
expansion of the “we” must be coaxed, not forced as a part of some divine or
universal plan. One modern pragmatist states, thusly,
After
long and unsatisfactory struggles with the search for a transcultural
foundation, there is something quite appealing about giving up the fight,
examining the consequences, and seeing that we can still say what we want, with
no worse effect. For example, by telling a non-liberal government that there
are naturally existing human rights, we are no better off or more convincing
than saying that, ‘from the perspective of my liberal culture, your citizens
are suffering at the hands of your government, and that is where I stand.’
Indeed, by undermining the universal moral authority of our claims about human
rights, we may even serve to enhance our powers of moral persuasion” (Cochran
165).
Pragmatism, then, prefers an approach to
national security interests that is less directly confrontational than pure
moral reasoning, but that takes moral influence more seriously than traditional
realism does. This indirect approach to security is to begin by accommodating
some competing interests and moral sentiments from the world at large, molding
them into a middle ground compromise which exactly matches neither our moral
baseline nor “theirs,” but resembles both to a great enough extent that it
secures the allegiance of the greatest number.
For the pragmatist, this is an unending but manageable task
and one worth undertaking, and it is best executed by combining strong national
advocacy with soft engagement.
This
is necessary because unilateral action in the face of international dissent is
too often counterproductive of the desired aims of that action. Often times a
“moral” course, such as the neoconservative drive for a democratic
All
the obvious prudential calculations about the costs of intervening, the
probability of winning, and the likely aftermath are morally necessary… It
would not have been just, for example, for the
Walzer’s very important contribution here is to assert that
morality and strategy are naturally intertwined and can never be wholly
separated: whether one “ought” to do something is very much a function of
whether one can succeed in doing it.
The interplay of morality and
strategy is not new: Clausewitz flatly stated in his magnum opus, On War,
that “no one starts a war – or rather, no one in his senses ought to do so –
without first being clear in his mind what he intends to achieve by that war
and how he intends to conduct it” (579). From this a pragmatist infers that we
should dispense with distinctions between jus
ad bellum and jus in bello, that
we should discard the notion that a war can be justly declared but poorly waged
in the event. It is not enough that military action seeks to right a wrong or intends
to bring about a state of security and stability; it must as well be reasonably
capable of doing so, without bringing about a worse state by its unintended
effects.
As we now see, when stripped of the
veneer of truth, moral considerations in waging war become wholly prudential. Building
upon this perspective, a pragmatist war convention will have to exercise greater
restraint both in identifying threats to security and in addressing them.
Certain traditional fixtures of just war theory will occasionally have to be ignored,
while others will take on a greater importance. For example, when a state
considers whether to prosecute unpopular actions in civilian-rich areas, the
rule of double-effect or unintended consequences, which absolves an army of
guilt for collateral damage caused in the pursuit of a military objective, will
have to take a back seat to the rules of proportional response and immunity for
non-combatants – for, even if heavenly justice absolves an army of
responsibility, the court of public opinion still holds forth on the issue, and
popular support is critical to the success of anti-terrorist and
counterinsurgency efforts. “Foreign assistance and a determined effort to
persuade hostile publics that the United States does not want to be an enemy
are crucial, not because they are likely to reduce the number of potential
terrorists to a safe number, but because they are likely to make it possible
for a friendly state to do that” (Heymann 2001, 27). As in Walzer’s Hungarian
example, if an action is likely to exact substantial human and material costs –
especially costs that can be witnessed by an international audience via mass
media – to achieve its tactical successes, the attacker risks too much in terms
of the moral power he will need to achieve ultimate victory, and the action should
be dismissed as strategically undesirable.
The consequences of this
philosophical turn for preemptive war are enormous. On the pragmatist view, it
is simply not enough to believe that a grave security threat exists, especially
if a global consensus cannot be reached on the threat’s imminence and gravity.
An actor considering preemption must carefully weigh that threat not only against
the material costs of intervention, but against the costs assigned to it by the
prevailing moral sentiments of the day. But as it was just suggested, even if
intervention is warranted by the nature of a threat, and even if that action is
tolerated by the international community, such toleration can turn quickly against
the intervening power if its actions exact too dear a cost on civilians,
property, or global sensibilities by their effects, intended or otherwise. No
matter what a particular account of justice or international law has to say
about preempting such a threat, if the action taken is unpopular, expensive,
and borne by only a few actors, its prospects for success are likely so limited
that it would be imprudent to act with overwhelming military force.
This is not to say that a prudent
posture would leave us wholly defenseless when a threat against us is not
recognized by a larger international community. For if pragmatists are serious
about working free of truth-obsessed, foundational thinking, they “would
facilitate thinking in terms of ranges rather than oppositions in regard
to questions about persons, states and the scope of ethical claims” (Cochran
166). Foundational thinking is more likely to yield static notions of what
constitutes a clear threat and what a clear response to it might look like. Just
war theory has always approached these critical terms of preemption in sterile
and largely unhelpful ways, assuming that state sovereignty, individual
freedom, or some other virtue is always the highest value and then
focusing on obvious military threats to it. The predictable result is a preoccupation
with large-scale (though proportional) military preemption. Such a perspective
rarely solves the common “hard cases”, where the nature of a threat, the proper
means to address it, indeed the core ethical presumptions that lead to threat
assessment, are all open to debate. Pragmatism, rather than dodging conflicts
of values, attempts to incorporate them into a prescription for political
action. Hence pragmatist theorists can offer a range of preemptive measures for
a range of perceived threats.
Walzer gives
us an example of this sliding scale of preemptive justice when he encourages us
to distinguish between states that actively partner with terrorists and states
that harbor them (or are rumored to do so). The right response in the latter
cases “involves measures short of war, which are likely to be most effective if
they are organized multilaterally. In fact, it should be a goal of US foreign
policy to mobilize international support for diplomatic, political, and
economic pressure on states that allow terrorist organizations to work from
their territory” (Walzer 2004, 38). Cultural diplomacy, economic incentives,
sanctions, blockades, covert action, and even isolated strategic air or ground
strikes can all be seen as preemptive instruments, each of which can address a
variety of situations and each of which is more likely to garner valuable global
support than the deployment of hundreds of thousands of troops to a trouble spot.
Nor is Walzer alone in this call for
moderation in choosing ends and means. Some of the most recent popular books by
political scientists have pressed for the
Any military
officer worth his or her salt will agree with Mao that it is asinine
generalship to limit one’s options unnecessarily in a struggle. But we do
precisely that by viewing morality as a reflection of truth rather than as a
powerful instrument for compelling others to accept our will. A far-sighted war
convention that favors American interests will hold the latter view. Its
advocates will call for restraint, consultation, and deliberation in threat
assessment, even and especially when preemptive action is considered. By
adopting such a convention, we will enhance our moral standing in the world,
increasing our “soft” power and lessening the need for “hard” military action
as a primary tool of foreign policy.
References
Clausewitz, Carl. 1989. On War. Michael Howard and Peter Paret,
eds.
Etzioni, Amitai. 2004. From Empire to Community: A New Approach
to International Relations.
Heymann, Philip B. 2001. Dealing With Terrorism.
International Security 26 No.3: 24-38.
Larmore, Charles. 1996. The Morals of Modernity.
Mao Tse-Tung. 1967. On Protracted War. The Selected Works of
Mao Tse-Tung.
Mill, John Stuart. 1963. Essays on Politics and Culture.
Gertrude Himmelfarb, ed.
Nye Jr., Joseph S. 2004. Soft Power: The Means to Success in
World Politics.
Posner, Richard. 2002. The Problematics of Moral and Legal
Theory.
Ries, Al and Trout, Jack. 2000. Positioning: The
Rorty, Richard. 1999. Philosophy and Social Hope.
Singer, Peter. 2004. One World.
Walzer, Michael. 1977. Just and Unjust Wars.
Walzer, Michael. 2004. Words of War:
Challenges to the Just War Theory. Harvard International Review 26: 37-41.
Wendt, Alexander. Anarchy Is What
States Make of It: The Social Construction of Power Politics. International
Organization 46: 391-425.