Submission for presentation at
The Joint Services Conference on Professional Ethics
Hilton Springfield Hotel,
Department of Leadership, Ethics, & Law
beyer@post.harvard.edu
(410) 757-5175
Introduction
In
service academies, in training, and in combat, much effort goes into imbuing
military personnel with the excellent character trait of courage. But what exactly is this virtue at which such
efforts aim? Consider any serious
gut-check situation: a recon patrol in
enemy-infested jungle; street-by-street urban warfare, cut off from one’s
larger unit; charging up Omaha Beach on D-Day; flying into a buzz-saw of
flak—what is the courage or bravery (I will use these terms interchangeably)
that we hope for in such dire circumstances?
Is the ultimate goal war-fighters who cope with and manage their fears,
face the threats, and persevere in performing their duties? Or war-fighters who encounter such situations
without experiencing fear, and hence without needing to handle it? Surely military training cannot be optimally
effective without a clear picture of what end result it intends to
produce.
According
to the Classical View of character, bequeathed to us by Aristotle and still
prevalent today, the virtue of courage involves at its heart the withstanding
and overcoming of reasonably
experienced fear. It is a disposition to
surmount, conquer, or master one’s ongoing fear when confronting circumstances
that are fearsome, that is, properly provoking of fear. On this standard conception, courage does not
allow, let alone require, an absence of fear in the face of fearsome
circumstances. One must face up to these
circumstances and stay the (right) course despite
the presence of fear. To lack fear
altogether is to be mad, or at least rash or out of control.
I maintain, however, that this
tradition of thinking about courage is mistaken—that the only persons properly
regarded as unqualifiedly brave are those who experience no fear while handling fearsome circumstances. However much we praise, and are impressed by,
those who overcome their fears, these persons are not exemplars of true
courage, but occupy an imperfect state that is somewhat defective.
After some brief further ground
clearing to get our terms straight, I will proceed by laying out the central
reasons for subscribing to the Classical View of courage as fear overcoming,
then present and explain the courage-as-fearlessness conception (“CAF”), and
finally attempt to head off objections to this alternative approach to
understanding courage.
Fear
I take fear to be the unpleasant,
aversive apprehension of a danger that threatens us (or someone or something with
which we strongly identify). The threat
is to something that we care about, and so would not want to lose. (Thus, someone who longs for escape from life
need not feel fear upon apprehending a threat to her life.) The full-blown experience of fear includes a
cognitive component (the perception or thought of the danger), an affective
component (the unpleasant feeling), and a physiological component (bodily
arousals of various sorts, though fainting is possible, too).
If we allow that the aversive threat
to self-interest may come either from physical dangers to life, bodily
integrity, and freedom from pain, as on the battlefield, or from non-physical
risks—social isolation or ostracism, loss of loved ones or of contact with
loved ones, shame or humiliation, financial loss, emotional exposure or
intimacy, career setbacks, and so on—then this conception of fear is
sufficiently broad to allow us to discuss all varieties of courage together,
including physical and moral (and perhaps others). [1]
So, is courage better understood to
be a stalwartness in the face of trepidation-inducing dangers, as the Classical
View maintains, or an intrepid stoutheartedness that recognizes dangers without
fear and gamely confronts them?
Arguments for the Classical View
There is a battery of reasons that
support the widespread belief that courage requires fear. Here is a survey of the major ones.
“[S]tanding firm against what is painful makes us
call people brave” (NE 1117a30-b20[2]).
“[T]he
man who does not fear the things he should, and neither when nor as he should,
is foolhardy” (EE 1221a15-20[3]).
“[I]f
he is afraid of nothing at all and goes to face everything, he becomes rash”
(NE 1104a20-23).
“The
person who is excessively fearless … would be some sort of madman, or incapable of feeling
distress, if he feared nothing, neither earthquake nor waves, as they say about
the Celts.” (NE 1115b25-30).
“[V]irtue
of character … aims at the intermediate condition in feelings and actions” (NE 1109a20-25).
“We
can be afraid, e.g., or be confident, or have appetites, or get angry, or feel
pity, … both too much and too little, …; but [having these feelings] at the
right times, about the right things, towards the right people, for the right
end, and in the right way, is the intermediate and best condition, and this is
proper to virtue. Similarly, actions also
admit of excess, deficiency and the intermediate condition” (NE 1106b18).
“In
feelings of fear and confidence the mean is bravery.” (NE 1107a30+-b5).
The Doctrine
of the Mean seems to require that courage involve fear; fearlessness would
appear to be a non-virtuous excess.
Courage as fearlessness
On the alternative conception that I
propose, the ideally or fully brave person habitually engages in mental
manipulations that manage to prevent the arousal (or perhaps continuation) of
fear, yet do not suppress the knowledge or ongoing awareness that is needed for
rational practical reasoning and action.
For example, on the battlefield, brave warrior W sees the enemy
soldiers, their proximity, their large weapons, their fevered eagerness to kill
him and his comrades, the dangers posed by those snipers over there. W is not unaware that there might be others
waiting to pounce from behind those bushes, and that his own gun has
jammed. He factors all of these
circumstances into his choices of behavior, and into his planning. Yet he feels no fear as he does so.
How is this possible? By cognizing the potential fear-inspiring
data ‘shallowly’—as one cognizes the information that one’s doctor is
presenting about one’s festering, life-threatening wound while one is
discussing intellectually with him what one’s options are, what actions one
ought to take (or not take), and so on.
One does not allow oneself to activate (occurrently accept) imagery that
would likely cause disgust, nausea, grief, or panic. One does not allow oneself to think of the
implications and consequences of one’s death, or, therefore, of the further
imagery that pertains to this. (It
follows, too, that second, third, and later levels of implications and consequences,
along with their attendant imagery, go unthought as well.) This extra information would not be relevant
to one’s task at hand—it would not significantly enhance one’s discussion and
planning in the doctor’s office. On the
other hand, its presence to mind could very well be distracting or debilitating
in a way that would undermine the current activity. At the very least, it would demand a great
effort of will to maintain one’s composure and focus adequately—effort that
could otherwise be directed in more productive directions. Consequently, one keeps one’s engagement with
the issues on a purely intellectual plane, thereby reproducing neither the
cognitive aspect of fear, nor the exact affective and physiological aspects
that accompany it.
Clearly, ordinary experience shows
that we are capable of this sort of shallow cognizing, though its presence has
gone unremarked in the philosophical literature. It offers a potential route—if perhaps not
the only route—to the attainment of fearlessness in the face of fearsome
circumstances.
Responding to the arguments
If vigilant fearlessness is the
mean, and heedlessness of relevant realities the excess, the deficiency is
experiencing action-inhibiting fear—cowardice—just as on the Classical View. But what of the Classical View’s ideal, of
being disposed to experience, but out-wrestle, fear? This is surely a greatly superior state to
simple cowardice, but it is only an intermediate, and ideally temporary and transitional,
point on the path to complete courage.
In this, it is parallel to other not-quite-virtues where individuals
reliably display the proper conduct, yet without having their feelings in
harmonious sync with such conduct. The fully
temperate person feels no pain in refraining from inappropriate bodily
pleasures (NE 1118b30-end); and the truly generous person’s giving is done
“with pleasure or [at any rate] without pain” (NE 1120a 25-30).
Moreover, do we really regard as a lunatic
the soldier who does not feel fear as s/he wades into battle, as suggested in
the earlier argument for the Classical View?
Or is this person actually our paragon of bravery, albeit one that most
of us cannot hope to emulate?
Moreover, fear actually is often a
performance degrader, not
enhancer. If the benefits of arousal can
be obtained without fear, then fearlessness would appear to be a superior state
for someone to be in when facing dangers, on the battlefield or elsewhere. (In selection of military personnel for
special forces assignments (e.g., Navy Seals), selectors tend to prefer those
whose psychological profiles reveal that they have somewhat reduced emotional
reactions.[5])
Fear
is the common bond between fighting men.
The overwhelming majority of soldiers experience fear during or before
battle: what vary are its physical
manifestations, its nature and intensity, the threat which induces it, and the
manner in which it is managed. Only a
tiny percentage of soldiers never know fear at all. (p.204)
We
ought to be studying the intrepid few, to see whether in fact they experience
no fear (rather than merely suppress it, leading to later breakdown) and, if
so, what we might learn about how to manufacture this state in those who are
not already inclined toward it.
Conclusion
It is important to state, in
conclusion, that conceiving of courage as fearlessness does not compel us to
deny the laudable, impressive achievements of those who experience and overcome
fear, or to deny that they deserve recognition for their trait of imperfect
courage (or maybe of some distinct related virtue involving determination or
will power).
It is not even clear that
fearlessness ought to be deemed as heroic as fear-overcoming. Consider another trait that bears some
relation to courage: selflessness. Selflessness sometimes involves deliberate
choice to set aside one’s own self-interests:
despite full awareness of the stakes for oneself, one makes the tough call. Selflessness can also be unthinking, however—spontaneous
acts done out of concern for others, with neglect for self. This latter variety is arguably a purer, more
ideal strain of selflessness, as the stakes for self are never even taken
notice of. It may also be easier to
attain, with training aimed at focusing one’s attention in certain situations,
rather than mainly at absorbing ideals of honor and exemplars of selfless
choice to be emulated. Yet the former
variety, of the deliberate sort, may therefore be, precisely because of its
imperfection, more awe-inspiring and laudable due to the difficulty brought by
the awareness involved, and the consequent need for direct strength of
will.
Courageous conduct may, similarly, be reachable by two roads—confronting
the dangers mentally, feeling the fears, yet still choosing to persevere, on
the one hand; and the less conscious courage as fearlessness, avoiding a full
psychological confrontation with the fearsome dimensions of one’s situation, on
the other. Some people might be better
suited to one than the other. Training
might differ for each, and the latter may possess a great untapped potential at
this point. It may also represent a
higher, more desirable ideal for humans to strive for. Still, though, the former—courage as
fear-overcoming—may be a more demanding and taxing achievement, and in that respect
more praiseworthy. So we need to keep to
keep distinct in our minds two issues:
what exactly constitute the human perfections that particular virtuous
character traits represent, and what moral evaluations are appropriate for
those who demonstrate either these virtues or the imperfect states that
resemble them.[7]
NOTES
[1]
The term “moral courage” is generally used
to refer to standing up for what one believes to be morally right, despite the
anticipated costs to one’s self-interests.
In my discussion of courage, I would ideally like to cover all acts
taken in the face of danger to self-interests, including non-physical ones, and
even where the acts are not primarily
motivated by moral concerns—say, a willingness to persevere in some
career-furthering act despite the serious threat this will pose to a friendship
or other relationship that one values, or maybe even where the act’s
aversiveness derives from the unfair harm that it will inflict upon an innocent
colleague.
[2] Citations to “NE” are to Aristotle’s Nichomachean Ethics, with section
references drawn from Terence Irwin’s 1985 translation for Hackett.
[3] Citations to “EE” are to Aristotle’s Eudemian Ethics, with section references
drawn the second edition of Michael Woods’ Clarendon Press translation of books
I, II, and VIII (1992), and from the Rackham
translation at http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/cgi-bin/ptext?lookup=Aristot.+Eud.+Eth.+<section
#>> (10-29-03), which is based upon Aristotle.
Aristotle in 23 Volumes, Vol. 20, trans.
H. Rackham. (Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press; London, William
Heinemann Ltd. 1981).
[4] See NE 1105b20+: “By feelings I mean appetite,
anger, fear, confidence, envy, joy, love, hate, longing, jealousy, pity, in
general whatever implies pleasure or pain.”
[5] Dr. Brad Johnson, USNA, personal
conversation.
[6]
Second edition, 2004 (formerly Firing Line, 1985).
[7]
My thanks go to Bob Fullinwider, Bob Schoultz,