UNITED
DEFINING JUST PREEMPTION
CDT CASSANDRA J. KEYES, ’07, CO C-2
ADVISOR: MAJ CHRISTOPHER MAYER
The concept of preemption in its modern application, notably the
The concept of preemption, defined as such, can be originally traced back to
Daniel Webster who said it was justly applied to situations in which there
existed an “instant [and] overwhelming” threat of aggression.[3]
This definition has since been modified by scholars such as Michael Walzer, professor of Social Science at the
Anticipatory acts that fail to satisfy any of the above conditions can then be
seen as preventive. This is because failure to satisfy any of the above
tenets means that a state is no longer preempting an inevitable act of
aggression but rather working to prevent against its possibility. A
product of 17th century
Some feel, including the Bush administration, that the only method of defending
against these types of dangers lies in a preemptive defense policy. In a
speech given for the American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research,
Charles Krauthammer discusses the option of preemption as “especially
necessary” given the underrable nature of terrorists
and the element of surprise they present.[9]
Preemption according to those who advocate this method of foreign policy,
however, is not the same preemption that Webster established or of which
Crawford speaks. It is actually preventive in nature. Krauthammer
goes on to say: “the point of preemption is to deter the very acquisition of WMDs in the first place.” This idea of attacking in
order to prevent a potential aggressor from gaining the capability to harm the
United States is not preemptive but preventive, using “malign intentions” as a
justification for attack without the need for substantiated proof of capability,
imminent threat, or the requirement of military force to avert
disaster. This sentiment is further reflected in the NSS when it
states that the
Primarily, an expanded definition of preemption fails to protect against any of the harms that have made preventive attack an unfavorable option in the eyes of the international community as reflected by the UN Charter, Article 51, which only recognizes a nation’s “inherent right” to self-defense against armed attack.[11] Not only a justification for blatant aggression, preventive war creates an international environment of fear, as well as nation-states, and increasingly terrorists, more likely to display increased aggression in response. Furthermore, given that preventive war, unlike preemption, does not necessarily require knowledge of the time and place of enemy attack nor a clear concept of exactly who the enemy is, it can make the distinction between combatants and non-combatants difficult.[12] Preemption also requires a specific understanding of what constitutes self-interest. Without this, nearly all preventive acts could be justified as self-defense when any of a number of non-essential aspects of statehood are threatened, making war an easy recourse. Justifying preventive acts as morally permissible preemptive actions also makes the consideration of non-military options less likely given the usually higher success rate and greater efficiency of military strikes—why negotiate with a potential enemy if you can eliminate it altogether, achieving greater security with less risk of attack. Pragmatically, there may be no reason to do so. However, morally, the sanctity of human life and the inherent right of nations to their political independence and territorial integrity obligates any nation considering preventive acts to also consider their moral implications.
Second, an expanded definition of preemption, as advocated by the NSS and Krauthammer, eliminates crucial criteria that have established preemption as a just form of anticipatory action. The legacy that created just war theory carries with it the weight of hundreds of years of legal, philosophical and religious contemplation on the subject of war and how to reconcile its brutality with that within man that desires peace and security. Thus, any reference to that tradition when discussing modern war and conflict also carries with it the weight of just war legacy. To expand the definition further and to allow leniency in its meaning would create a defense dynamic that Webster’s definition attempts to prevent—defense based on suspicion, not intention of hostile action. Just war theory draws a natural divide between moral consideration in war and the realist approach to preventative wars as “normal, even common, tools of statecraft…”[13] To use the one as a disguise to make the other acceptable is to abuse the natural intent of just preemption and to begin a gradual process of rendering it void of true meaning.
The NSS attempts to revise the concept of preemption in a way that allows for
US foreign policy to slide over the already vague line between preemption and
prevention. The National Security Strategy states: “[W]e must adapt the
concept of imminent threat to the capabilities and objectives of today’s adversaries…
taking anticipatory action to defend ourselves, even if uncertainty remains as
to the time and place of the enemy’s attack.”[14]
The danger in this stance is that it makes the definition of imminent threat
infinitely regressive. If a threat can be assumed imminent because no
evidence exists to prove it otherwise, the potential aggressor becomes guilty
and punishable by default—the reverse logic of all American jurisprudence,
which assumes innocence until guilt is proven. This would allow the
United States to attack nearly anywhere in the world with relatively
unsubstantiated claims of emerging threats. This is the danger of
preventive actions: they can easily slip into justification of naked
aggression. However, it may also be unreasonable to expect the
While it is possible that there may be a case for just prevention, it is valuable to understand the need to syntactically distinguish preemption from prevention. The justification for preemption, if it adheres to Crawford’s or Webster’s definitions, is clear and invariably persuasive as a moral act of self-defense available as an option to any country. This justification can only be retained if the integrity of these definitions is maintained. Thus, preemption should remain a distinct category of anticipatory actions available to a country. Given that there may also be a case for just prevention, the objective is now to determine the circumstances under which prevention is justified, and where the line lies that would distinguish just prevention from unjust prevention.
The three cases that distinguish themselves are the threats that emerge from terrorists, rouge nations, and countries that harbor terrorists. Most other threats a nation can defend itself against by adhering strictly to preemptive measures or other modes of defense and negotiation. In the case of terrorism, terrorist networks who have recently engaged in specifically known terrorist activities are not protected by just war theory as they have taken part in explicitly criminal activities, thus strike is legitimized at any time as long as it is winnable and proportional. When a terrorist group is known to exist but is idle, the rules for just anticipation do apply. This would be considered just prevention as the concept of “imminence” becomes nearly impossible to establish given a world in which terrorists operate by surprise and can strike at any place, at any time. While defensive measures can play some role in deterring this, the rise of the suicide bomber further exacerbates the problem. A nation should have the right to provide itself with some level of defense without having to overcome the sometimes impossible task of proving that an inevitable attack is coming in days or weeks. However, there must exist some check as “paranoid aggression promises endless war.”[16] In order to justify a preventive attack against terrorist networks, all that should have to be established is that there is aggressive intent and that the capacity exists to do harm. As Walzer discusses, “Randomness is the crucial feature of terrorist activity.”[17] A state should not have to prove that the attack is inevitable or necessarily immediate before it can justify actions of self-defense so long as they are proportional and likely to succeed.
The second issue lies with rogue nations. Michael Klare,
professor of Peace and World Security Studies in
The third threat comes from nations who harbor terrorists. The NSS states: “We make no distinction between terrorists and those who knowingly harbor or provide aid to them.”[19] While this may seem justified given the defense of preventive action against terrorists above, the Security Strategy’s stance that no distinction is to be made is actually the type of “paranoid aggression” of which Crawford speaks.[20] A distinction is necessary because while terrorists do not have any claims to political independence or territorial integrity, nations do. While terrorists forfeit many of their rights at the point at which they endanger and kill innocent civilians, nations who harbor them must be evaluated differently. Primarily, a nation must be supporting them knowingly and maliciously, they must be fully cognizant of the role they have in supporting whatever terrorists may reside within their borders or to whom they are providing aid. Secondly, they must be a main source of livelihood for the terrorists and it must be sanctioned by the government itself, not from those loosely connected with, but not a part of, the government. If the nation plays a small role in the terrorist organization’s livelihood and only provides an inconsequential amount of aid or sanctuary, anticipatory actions are not warranted. However, if the nation is the lifeblood of a terrorist organization, if diplomatic efforts have been exhausted for it to relinquish that aid, and if there is justified fear that the terrorists who rely upon it are a realistic threat, preventive attack on the nation is warranted even though the nation itself does not present a imminent threat to the anticipating nation’s self-defense.
Though the NSS is correct in stating that the concept of imminent threat must be adapted to modern adversaries, it does not delineate any standard for a new concept of imminent threat. The dilemma that has occurred as a result is that there is no existing standard to which the administration can be held by the American people or the international community. A second problem that has occurred is that, as a result of the misapplication of preemption to fit the need for a new definition of imminent threat, the concept has lost a great deal of its legitimacy as a just form of anticipatory action. The solution to both these problems is two fold: primarily, there must be a clear, lucid definition of preemption that is distinct and categorically independent of preventive acts. Second, the concept of just prevention must be explored as a means by which a nation can defend itself legitimately in the case that preemption is inadequate to maintain a reasonable level of self-defense against modern aggressors. While just war theory has discussed both subjects, it must specifically adapt itself to these specific issues. This paper is one proposal for both solutions. The underlying aim, however, is to bring to light the importance of the distinction itself. If a clear concept of preemption is maintained and the conditions that must be met to legitimize it are clear, it will carry with it the potent ideas of justice in self-defense and moderation and clear-headedness in war every time it is invoked. The danger that is identified here is that without a clear definition of preemption and what gives it legitimacy, the door is opened for the justification of unjust actions by way of a blurred idea of what is acceptable anticipatory action and what is not. If that clear definition does not exist, the idea of preemption will be void of meaning in the context of justice in war and legitimate cause. Clearly defined, preemptive action is not morally problematic but, in fact, always a moral recourse if specific criteria are present. Furthermore, there are instances in the modern world of threats that fall outside preemption and justify preventive anticipatory action, specifically the threats of terrorism and rouge nations. A clear definition dividing just prevention and unjust prevention is also necessary to ensure that a clear idea of just anticipatory actions is maintained. For fairness and justice in war to be upheld, this clarity is essential. Defining just preemption and just prevention is one such clarification to ensure that legitimacy is maintained.
Bibliography
Betts, Richard. “Striking First: A History of Thankfully Lost Opportunities.” Ethics and International Affairs 17, no 1 (2003): 1-4.
-------, Surprise Attack: Lessons for Defense Planning.
Charter of the United Nations, Article 51.
Crawford
Neta C. “The Best Defense: The problem with
Bush’s “preemptive” war doctrine.”
Klare, Michael. “The Rise and Fall
of the “Rogue Doctrine”: The Pentagon’s Quest for a Post-Cold War Military
Strategy.”
Krauthammer,
Charles. “An American Foreign Policy for a Unipolar World.” 2004 Irving Kristol Lecture.
Levy, Jack S. “Declining Power and the Preventive Motivation for War.” World Politics 40, no 1 (1987).
National Security Strategy of the
Reiter, Dan. “Exploding the Powder Keg Myth: Preemptive Wars Almost Never Happen.” International Security 20 (1995): 5-34.
Silverstone, Scott. Discussion with Dr. Silverstone, assistant Professor, USMA, regarding preventive and preemptive war. October 2004.
Walzer, Michael. Just and Unjust
Wars.
Worley,
Robert D. “Waging Ancient War: Limits on Preemptive Force.”
Strategic Studies Institute, US
NOTES
[1] Richard Betts. “Striking First: A History of Thankfully Lost Opportunities.” Ethics and International Affairs 17, no 1 (2003): 1.
[2] Dr. Scott Silverstone. Discussion with Dr. Silverstone, assistant Professor, USMA, regarding preventive and preemptive war. October 2004.
[3]
Michael Walzer. Just and
Unjust Wars. (
[4] Ibid, 85.
[5] Richard K. Betts. Surprise Attack: Lessons for Defense Planning (Wasington D.C.: Brookings Institution, 1982): pp.14-43.
[6] Neta C. Crawford. “The Best Defense: The problem with
Bush’s “preemptive” war doctrine.”
[7]
Robert D. Worley. “Waging Ancient War: Limits on Preemptive Force.”
Strategic Studies Institute, US
[8] National Security Strategy of the
[9] Charles
Krauthammer. “An American Foreign Policy for a Unipolar World.” 2004 Irving Kristol Lecture. (
[10] NSS, 14.
[11] Charter of the United Nations, Chapter 7, Article 51. (New York: United Nations, 1945).
[12] Crawford, 9.
[13] Jack S. Levy. “Declining Power and the Preventive Motivation for War.” World Politics 40, no 1 (1987): 84.
[14] NSS, 15.
[15] Dan Reiter. “Exploding the Powder Keg Myth: Preemptive Wars Almost Never Happen.” International Security 20 (Fall 1995): 5-34.
[16] Crawford, 5.
[17] Walzer, 197.
[18]
Michael Klare. “The Rise and Fall
of the “Rogue Doctrine”: The Pentagon’s Quest for a Post-Cold War Military
Strategy.”
[19] NSS, 5.
[20] Crawford, 5.