Birth of a Nation:
Planning for Regime Change Operations
Dr. Timothy L. Challans
School of Advanced Military Studies (SAMS)
tim.challans@jhu.edu
The Third of May, 1808 by Goya
Two hundred years
ago, French troops found themselves intractably fighting Spanish
guerrillas. Not insignificantly, the
term guerrilla was coined during this
conflict, Napoleon’s Peninsular War, the term deriving from the Spanish meaning
“little war.” The fighting devolved to a
level of barbarity such that both the Spanish guerrillas and the occupying
French troops were committing atrocities with equal enthusiasm and expertise. The atrocities inspired Goya to paint some of
his more disturbing works. At first, uprisings
were spontaneous, and it took years before anyone understood the scope and
nature of the growing insurgency. The
French people at home were told that the Spanish people would welcome the
regime change imposed by Napoleon, for who could argue against the benevolent
imposition of a superior French culture and way of life to rescue the backward
superstitious peasants of the Iberian Peninsula? It took two years for the guerrilla movement
to organize. After six years of
fighting, the French Army lost more troops in Spain
than in Russia. Out of the 250,000 troops who died in Spain,
145,000 of them were killed fighting the guerrillas. When recounting Spain,
Napoleon said, “That unfortunate war destroyed me…All…my disasters are bound up
in that fatal knot.”[1]
The French bashers
who would chalk off this loss of 150,000 troops to the stupidity or
recalcitrance of the French should consider that America
got a third of the way there in Vietnam
when they got entrenched in a guerrilla war because of an illegitimate regime
change operation. Before anyone
dismisses this historical event as being completely irrelevant today, they
should first ask if any of the relations among states of affairs within the
analogy present any insights we should think about. Of course there are dissimilarities; no
analogy presents an identical relationship.
The question of whether things are going well in the current American regime
change operations is a viable one. Those
in charge today tell us that “freedom is on the march.” Women are now voting in Afghanistan. We’re supposed to be reassured that three
fourths of the Al Qaeda leadership has been captured or killed. Our Commander-in-Chief asks, “"Who could
possibly think that the world would be better off with Saddam Hussein still in
power?" Well, an answer could be those
who are capable of a complex moral evaluation that rises above the adolescent
rhetoric of good and evil. It could
include anyone who values means as well as ends, or anyone who recognizes the
gravity of principle, the rule of law, or processes within constitutional
republics. It may even include the most
Machiavellian consequentialists, as long as they are capable of calculating the
consequences of more than one consequence at a time. But the establishment has been in utter
denial regarding even the potential of a substantial insurgency taking root;
the attacks are conducted either by a few remnant loyalists or by
outsiders—they just can’t be part of an Iraqi guerrilla movement. Just weeks ago on the anniversary of “a day
that shall live in infamy,” the infamous Oliver North reassured a veteran
audience that things were better at this point in time in this war than they
were at a comparable time during WWII.
North dismissed the possibility of a legitimate Iraqi insurgency as he
listed a dozen other countries that were providing all the insurgents. Many officials will continue to think there
are dozens or hundreds or maybe a few thousands of Iraqi insurgents when there
are more likely hundreds of thousands of them.
These same officials will not want to admit that there are more
terrorists today, sticking straight to their story that there are maybe dozens
or hundreds of Al Qaeda members when they more likely number in the tens of
thousands. No matter how the
recalcitrants manipulate the utilitarian calculus, it’s hard to avoid the
conclusion that the world is in many significant ways a more dangerous place
because of the regime change operations.
Many interesting
questions arise when considering regime change operations. Is the phenomenon a new one? If it is not new, what can we learn from its
use in history? Is it practical or is it
counterproductive? Is it justifiable or
not, right or wrong, good or bad? Is the
rule of force that a regime change
operation entails necessarily a departure from the rule of law? By the end of
this essay some preliminary sketches will emerge that begin to answer these
questions. However, the main questions I
will focus on have to with planning for regime change operations. We think of assigning moral praise and blame
once agents have acted, but we have not paid much attention to the role that
moral thinking should play during the planning of regime change operations, or
of any operation, for that matter. If we
have the made the world worse off through the doctrine of regime change, then
we should evaluate the process of regime change. When does a regime change operation
begin? Does it start when the troops
cross the line of departure? Or does it
start very early on, when American leaders identify a state as a security
threat, when a rogue state has crossed the line, aligning itself on an axis of
evil? Or does it begin somewhere in
between? When it was time for the
military to start planning the regime change in Afghanistan,
their job was to figure out the plan and then to execute it. And when it was time to start planning the
regime change in Iraq,
they did their job there, too. And
should they be told by their civilian bosses to start planning for the next
regime change, they will follow suit.
Regime change begins as a political crusade. The political leaders decide that the
political renewal of a nation can only be achieved by the military. And we have the birth of a nation, or the
rebirth of a nation. As moral agents,
all political and military leaders share moral responsibility for regime change
operations, throughout the operation and beyond, but particularly during the
planning phase. Current operational design systems that generate operational plans neither
facilitate moral agency nor distribute moral responsibility fittingly.
The normal
distinction between jus ad bellum and
jus in bello may no
longer be adequate when considering regime change operations. There have been recent attempts to add jus post bellum to complete the division
of labor so that the Just War Tradition can do its job fully. This triad divides the justice of conflict up
temporally: before, during, and after war.
However, it does not cleanly divide up the moral agency and
responsibility among people, institutions, agencies, or states involved in
those conflicts. Moral agency and the
moral responsibility of these different entities cut across the triad. There is a general trend in the Just War
Tradition to assign political leaders the responsibility of jus ad bellum and military leaders the responsibility
of jus in bello. Yet, even Walzer’s explication of this
distinction in his framework admits of an exception that may be large enough to
threaten the rule. Specifically, in Just and Unjust Wars, he sets about
showing the logical and practical distinctness of jus ad bellum and jus in bello with
separate parts in his book. He then adds
another entire part to his book explaining that the two species of justice
merge and overlap in many significant ways.
So, after he enumerates the constitutive and individuating principles
that separate the two domains into different species, he has to admit that the
differentia are threatened by numerous transcategorical and metacategorical
principles, making the two realms far less separate than the original framework
suggests.
How do they
merge? Is there any question that military
leaders can influence jus ad bellum
catastrophes? We need only be reminded
of the convicted felon Oliver North and his role as a military officer in the
counter-insurgency during the “first war against terrorism” under the Reagan
administration as they attempted illegal and misguided regime change operations
in Central America.
Alternatively, it’s been said that the road to Abu Ghraib has been paved
by memos from the White House. In the
first case, a marine lieutenant colonel was directly influencing jus ad bellum transgressions, and, in
the second political leaders were directly influencing jus in bello
violations. The White House is not the
only nexus where traditional roles and responsibilities become blurred between
political and military leaders. There
are many cases in which moral responsibility crosses this line. The culpability, complicity, and
responsibility of military and political leaders in such cases that go morally
awry should remain the subject of serious debate and investigation. Oliver North now enjoys celebrity status
despite his role while no political leaders were found culpable for the
Iran-Contra scandal. Under the penumbra
of Abu Ghraib today, only low-level troops will be held responsible for the
system of detention and mistreatment while Rumsfeld gets another term of office
and Gonzales becomes the attorney general.
The system perpetuates the distinction protecting military leaders from
responsibility for crimes at the political level as well as political leaders
from responsibility for crimes at the military level. The system continues to thwart the assignment
of responsibility, thereby threatening the whole notion of moral agency.
Should we accept
this distinction as Paul Christopher lays it out? He argues that political leaders do and
should remain responsible for jus ad bellum
issues and military leaders for jus in
bello issues, that officers should not cross this line and influence jus ad bellum issues, and that military
officers should consider the jus ad
bellum issues resolved and the conflict formally just by the time the
mission is handed over to them. In other
words, the military leaders have no role in jus
ad bellum questions. The Just War
Tradition along with its temporal division of jus ad bellum and jus in bello
perpetuates this problem, because the former concerns itself with those matters
occurring before the war (and hence remain political issues alone) and the
latter with matters once the conflict begins (and hence remain military issues
alone). Perhaps it is time to question
this distinction more strongly.
The current
framework of an operation may be part of the problem. There is a temporal continuum for a regime
change operation—before, during, and after—broken into phases. But, perhaps even more important for this
inquiry, there is also a hierarchical continuum, spanning the different levels
of conflict: from the highest strategic
level to the lowest tactical level and including the operational level in
between that links the other two. I say
that the latter is perhaps more important because the leaders throughout the
institutions involved are moral agents and as such have moral agency. We can investigate the moral agency and
responsibility of these moral agents by looking at the framework of these
political and military levels of conflict—and levels of responsibility. An acetate graphic dividing the political
realm from the military was permanently fixed to the moral map dividing the
realm of jus ad bellum and jus in bello in the
modern Trinitarian Age. The military
trinitarian world emerged from the Newtonian universe, a universe of cause and
effect, with order, where human, social, and political categories were carved
neatly at the joints. Clausewitz echoed
the Kantian and notion that war is an activity of the state, that war is
connected to the state, that military affairs are the province of the state, or
in Clausewitz’s terms that war is a continuation of state policy by other
means. Most people believe that this
truism is so obvious it barely needs repeating.
The notion that military affairs are an extension of political affairs
happens to be only possible arrangement.
Another possibility is that the two are completely separate, as was the
case in Sun Tzu’s world. And yet another
possibility is that they are the same thing, as they happened to be in Mao’s
world. The Newtonian hierarchy that
cleanly separates the political from military affairs may no longer be
explanatory or operative or constructive.
In the Newtonian, trinitarian universe, political leaders have
(ostensibly) the moral agency and moral responsibility for jus ad bellum issues and military leaders have (ostensibly) the
moral agency and moral responsibility for jus
in bello issues. The political and
military domains overlap so significantly today that it no longer makes sense to
view their overlapping as anomalous, but following Kuhn the interdependency between
the two should signal the need for a new paradigm. Political and military leaders influence
ethical matters in both the political and military realms. Therefore, political and military leaders
share moral agency in both the political and military realms at all stages of a
regime change operation. Following this
state of affairs, it may be time to address the issue of also assigning them
moral responsibility. Military leaders
can and do influence the political process in going to war and political
leaders can and do influence the military affairs once the conflict
begins. After a conflict begins,
military leaders can continue to influence the political realm, and they often
are a large part of the political realm during Phase IV of an operation—known
as the post-conflict phase. This fact is
especially clear when one admits that Phase IV begins as soon as the troops
cross the line of departure.
Military
responsibility in military affairs is especially relevant while developing
operational plans. American military
planners through their training and education should know that their planning
should be at a minimum morally bound by the legal framework of the laws of
war. Many planning staffs and cells have
JAG officers in them to help stay within legal boundaries. Legal expertise notwithstanding, military
operations pose many problems for keeping conflicts both legal and moral. Rules of Engagement are at times used instead
of the laws themselves. JAG officers
will interpret laws and ROE differently.
Commanders are not bound to follow the advice of these lawyers. And we all know that the legal does not
equate to the moral. As Paul Christopher
notes, “the relevant military manual advises soldiers to obey only lawful
orders, while at the same time acknowledging that they often will be unable to
tell lawful orders from unlawful ones!”[2] My own informal survey of awareness of the
laws of war for both cadets at West Point and majors at
CGSC show that there is at best only a moderate commitment to the laws of war
and the moral principles that support those laws. The following chart shows a comparison of the
level of awareness of these laws.
Appreciation for the Laws of War
Controversially, I
am arguing that military responsibility in political affairs is also relevant
during the planning phase of a regime change operation. If it is true that both political and
military leaders can and should influence and exercise agency during all phases
of an operation, then we should more fully understand and come to grips with
what the military’s role should be in the political realm. The American military has a long history with
regime change operations. If these
operations appear to be a new way of doing business, it is only because they
are now overtly proclaimed in our national security and military strategies
where they used to be covert. Prior to
WWI, American leaders thought their greatest threat was Mexico. The military drew up plans to defend against Mexico
by attacking Mexico
and installing a new regime. Perhaps
Vince Lombardi got some of his ideas by studying American history. The history of the South America
and the Caribbean during the first half of the last
century is one long saga of regime change operations. Since the end of WWII, there have been at
least thirty regime change operations, which have ranged from propaganda
campaigns and ballot tamperings to assassinations to covert coups to full-blown
military operations. There is only one
American president in the last century who did not attempt a regime change
operation, President Carter. The number
of regime change operations would be hard to count, and the number of plans for
these operations as well as the much larger number of plans for contingency
operations would be all the more difficult to grasp. How many of these plans spent any time on
moral considerations? How many of these
were blatantly illegal? Did the planners
for the Bay of Pigs Operation spend any time considering the restraints of
international law? And how about the
planners for Operation Northwoods? When
the military plan for the regime change in Afghanistan
called for the use of proxy forces, did the planners consider how this plan ran
counter to the political goal?
Specifically, if the political goal is to eliminate rule by warlords,
then how does the military plan support that goal when it simply empowers other
warlords? Today Afghanistan
remains more aptly named Warlordistan. What
is the ontological status of a plan? In
other words, when does it become real?
While it sits on a shelf, does its reality exist in its potential, or
does it become real only when it gets implemented? Don’t plans imply intent? And isn’t intent part of the moral
evaluation?
What happens if we
don’t consider this new direction? Well,
more and more and more of the same. The
military is shouldering more of the moral burden of regime change operations
than it deserves. It is taking on more
of the moral responsibility without the commensurate moral agency. We are in this unfortunate situation right
now because political leaders are not taking responsibility for the moral
agency they are exercising. So, since
agency crosses the traditional line between political and military leaders,
then so should responsibility. Moral
agency and moral responsibility should correspond. It is the planning system itself that needs
improvement. The military leaders are
doing the best they can with the system they are given. But the military should spend some time
rethinking and retooling their planning systems so that America
can better ensure that her military operations match the high moral standards
in her rhetoric. I am not now proposing
how this can be done at this point. I am
only arguing that there is a case that it should be done, that we study this to
understand it better and then genuinely consider possibilities that approach
how it can be done. Today the military
plans for and executes the operation, removing a regime so a nation can be
born, or for those fundamentalist minds now in charge who think in biblical terms,
perhaps reborn. These recent births have
been so violent that both mother and father have been killed in the
process. We all hope that whatever
nations are born by these regime changes can survive their births and continue
to live on their own, that they not become still-born. We still do not know for sure if these births
will succeed in some fashion. We do know
that they have not succeeded according to the plan, which means that there was
something wrong with the plan. All I am
suggesting is that there is room for improvement. So, if you see a car with two “Support our
Troops” ribbons along with a bumper sticker that says, “Stop Abortions Now,” as
I saw the other day driving onto Fort Leavenworth, you should stop
wondering—the driver is not conscious of the potential irony.
NOTES