HOSTING TERROR:
HOW THE PRESENCE OF TERROR GROUPS
AFFECTS THE ETHICS OF INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS AND INTERVENTION
CADET JACOB M. BRADY[1]
USMA WEST POINT
In a recent
article in Foreign Policy magazine,
Stephen D. Krasner presents a hypothetical scenario in which terrorists
detonate nuclear devices in major cities around the world and he then discusses
the likely impact that such a horrific event would have on the current
international system.[2] No doubt, Krasner is right to suggest that
such an event would likely make quaint many of the notions of sovereignty that
have guided the relations among states since the creation of the Westphalian
system. As powerful states faced the
reality of tens or hundreds of thousands of dead citizens, they would likely
not feel constrained by traditional barriers against intervention. However, as it currently stands, and despite
the attacks on the
Despite being
stateless actors, international terror groups do depend, in large part, on host
states where they can organize terrorist campaigns against civilian populations. When the “host state” is the sole target of
this violence, I believe that traditional classifications and distinctions
about sovereignty, insurgencies, and terrorist movements (like those explored
by Michael Walzer in Just and Unjust Wars)
address these circumstances sufficiently.
However, when the host state is not the sole target of terrorist
violence, or is not even a target at all, the situation changes, and other
states are forced to take notice of the internal circumstances within other
sovereign nations. It is these sorts of
circumstances that the current international system, the system that Walzer designates
as the “legalist paradigm,”[3]
fails to properly adjudicate.
Specifically, Walzer and others fail to address how a potential “target
state” may interact with what I will call “host states,” or those states where
terrorists take refuge, in order to effectively address terrorist threats. Despite the reality that serious attacks by
terrorists using Weapons of Mass Destruction (WMD) somewhere in the world would
likely make moral arguments about preventive war take a back seat to serious
questions of national self-interest in most peoples’ minds, the moral questions
about intervention remain in the foreground for those of us who believe any
legitimate policy must remain solidly rooted in ethical concepts. For this reason, I intend to lay out an
intellectual scaffolding to assist the moral discussion about any potential
change in international norms and policies.
I propose creating a “Continuum of Complicity” to direct the actions
that potential target states may take in dealing with the sovereignty of other
nations. I believe that the degree of
complicity that a host state shows with a terrorist group is integral to
determining the actions that a potential target state may take with another,
sovereign host state. This continuum has
two poles: at one end of the continuum exist host states that unwillingly or
unwittingly host terrorist groups, or “unwilling states” for ease of
discussion; at the other pole exist host states that actively assist terrorist
groups within their borders, or “accomplice states.” A reasonable determination by states as to
where a host state falls on this continuum helps to determine the level of
action that may be taken against that host state to counter the threat of
terrorism. Importantly, this discrimination
is not the sole determiner of action:
traditional just war criteria such as right intention, right authority,
proportionality, and reasonable hope for success still apply. However, the nature of the relationship
between sovereign governments and the terrorist groups that operate within
their borders does provide another category for states to appraise as they
determine the justice of their potential actions in response to terrorism.
Conceptually,
it is important to begin any discussion of terrorist organizations by showing
the similarities and differences between them and other stateless
Non-Governmental Organizations (NGOs), and then to define what a terror group
is and how it affects the ethical considerations of international relations. Like most NGOs, the goal of terror groups is
to affect some form of political or policy change at the state level. However, fundamental differences exist that
preclude terror groups from interacting with states in the same way traditional
NGOs do. Of course, the crux of these
differences lies in methodology. At
their core, terror groups seek to “destroy the morale of a nation” in order to
achieve political change.[4] By using “the random murder of innocent
people,” terror groups have forfeited the rights and protections afforded NGOs.[5] Terror groups seek to affect some sort of
political or policy change in sovereign and recognized states by
indiscriminately attacking the noncombatant population of that state.[6]
However, terror groups lack territorial integrity of their own and, for this
paper to be applicable to them, act independent of the directions (but not
necessarily funding) of a state hierarchy.
Like traditional NGOs, terror groups possess the ability to exist in any
state, with or without the consent of the host state. By existing within the borders of a state,
terror groups try to protect themselves against foreign attacks by exploiting
the territorial integrity of the host state and other states’ prohibition
against intervention.[7] This parasitic relationship offers a de facto
safe haven for terror groups since outside states are only authorized to
intervene under the most exceptional circumstances, according to just war
theory.[8] While Walzer defines “terrorism” he fails to examine
how the presence of a terror group within the territory of a state affects
international relations and intervention.
Having defined
“terror group,” I must now determine how the presence of terror groups changes
the ethical considerations of international relations. In order to determine how a state may act
towards a host state, the host state must be located on the “Continuum of
Complicity.” As I indicated earlier,
this continuum measures, as its name suggests, the degree of complicity between
a state and the terror groups it hosts.
In order to help visualize this continuum, three markers are
needed. At one extreme on the continuum
is the unwilling host who actively and effectively pursues and prosecutes
terror groups within its borders. States
like
While
host states are often a target of the terrorists they prosecute, the export of
terror forces these states to accept a role as an active member of the
international community. Not only do the
terror groups operate in, and attack the host state, they use the host state to
plan or stage terror attacks against other states. As long as the unwilling host actively and
effectively prosecutes the terror groups within its borders, intervention is
only permitted at the request of the host state government. By effectively prosecuting known terror
groups, the host state maintains its right to political sovereignty and
territorial integrity. I will deal with
how a target state may interact with an unwilling host who can not effectively
prosecute the terrorists within its borders later in this paper. Naturally, the definition of effective
prosecution of terror groups is open to interpretation, but a reasonable and
responsible judgment must be made in order to classify the host state.
The
next marker or range on the continuum is difficult to both define and identify
practically. The ambivalent state is one
that allows terror groups to stage out of its territory, but does not provide
actual material support of those terror groups. Ambivalent states have clearly chosen to
ignore the moral mandate to prevent the export of terror, and it is in this
negligence that Walzer’s shortcomings are especially apparent in traditional
accounts. Intervening against the government,
itself, would not be justified since the state does not provide material
support to the terrorists, but the target state can not sit idly and allow
terrorists a geo-political safe haven.
It would be a violation of the target state’s obligations to its people
to ignore the very real danger that this circumstance presents. I propose that in cases where we see
ambivalent host states, all reasonable political means must be exhausted before
any military intervention may be permitted.
Should peaceful means fail to convince the ambivalent host to cease the
export of terror, then limited military strikes are permissible. These strikes must be limited to terror
groups and not state entities or agencies.
These military strikes must be limited in scope and specific in
targeting. Military strikes within the
territory of a sovereign state that hosts terror are only permissible when all
reasonable peaceful options have been exhausted and are an exception to
non-intervention rather than a rule.
The
last state is often the most difficult to deal with in the diplomatic world,
but rather simple to deal with ethically.
The willing host provides not only geo-political sanctuary to terror
groups, but it also provides material support.
This support constitutes a sponsorship of terror and incurs the obvious
responsibility for the actions of those terrorists that the state
sponsors. State-sponsored terror is a
direct and real threat to other sovereign states and must not be
tolerated. In these cases, states have
gone beyond ignoring the obligation to prosecute terror groups within their
borders and have accepted responsibility for the outcome of the actions of the
terrorists, both planned and realized. Clearly
accomplice states are rarely, if ever, subject to attacks by the terror groups
they sponsor. This near immunity from
attack, however, does not absolve them from the repercussions of terror attacks
elsewhere. If a state provides material
support to a known terror group, then that state must be party to actions
committed by the terror groups while sponsored by the host state. This responsibility opens the accomplice
state up to the possibility of unilateral preemptive intervention.
While
these three defined points on the continuum serve as a guide to placing a state
on the continuum, they are not the only possible positions a state can hold. Yet, the three markers all have relatively
consistent traits. In other words, they
are all easily classified and placed.
Unfortunately no state in the world
is so easily defined. Perhaps the most
immediate example of this, and of particular import to the
As
a matter of course, challenges to the continuum will rise, and must be
addressed for the continuum to hold any validity. The strongest argument against the continuum
is that target states can never have perfect knowledge of the relationship
between terrorists and their host state, nor can the target states ever divine,
with perfect clarity, the intent of the terror groups it seeks to
prosecute. The argument goes that this
imperfect knowledge would allow target states to attack terror groups based on
circumstantial evidence and possible coincidence. Naturally this would increase
violence and unwarranted intervention which most ethicists accept as bad. And it is true that, in a vacuum, the
continuum could be used to validate almost any intervention. Conceivably a target state could act based on
misinformation or flawed logic, and do so repeatedly. However, the continuum does not exist in a
vacuum. Far from it, the continuum is
merely one simple tool with which the target state may analyze potential
actions. It is entirely possible that
the continuum will indicate that intervention is permissible, but that a target
state, cognizant of its own imperfect knowledge and its calculations of
proportionality, will decide that, overall, intervention is not warranted. I feel it important to note here that Walzer’s
principles defining prevention and preemption still apply, and any preemptive
intervention must abide by his standards for anticipation. Another criticism of the continuum might
revolve around the ambivalent state. While
the willing support of terrorism clearly constitutes a threat to the target
state, and unwilling states actively combat terrorism, the ambivalent host
presents a more perplexing ethical dilemma:
the question rises of why an ambivalent state gains greater protection
against intervention than does the willing host, yet less merits protection
than the unwilling host. Ambivalent
hosts certainly present less of a threat than willing hosts, but intervention
is still permitted. Intervention is
permitted because of the threat terrorism presents to not only the target
state’s government, but to its civil society.
While imperfect knowledge would permit the continuum to be used in
almost any situation, and abuse of the continuum is possible, other factors,
such as right intent, reasonable chance for success, proportionality, and
competent authority that still apply to intervention in general mitigate the
danger of this. That is not to say that
states do not need to gain knowledge prior to acting. Indeed, I feel that they must do so to the fullest
reasonable extent of their abilities.
Consequently, the continuum must be viewed as a piece of a whole and can
not simply replace just war theory, but must augment it.
I believe that
this continuum provides us with a conceptual framework that we can use to help
evaluate when it is permissible to intervene against terrorism in other
states. As I stated before, this
continuum is not intended to replace just war theory but provide us with an
additional ethical tool. Location on the
continuum does not exclusively determine whether or not military intervention
against terrorism is permissible, but it does provide us a moral vocabulary to
assist in discussions to determine this permissibility. Without the other established just war
criteria, it is certainly possible that governments could abuse the continuum
and use it to justify nearly any action, or to knowingly provide false evidence
that would support intervention based on the continuum. In short the imprecise nature of the
continuum makes it far too vulnerable to be used as the sole discriminator in
determining the ethical propriety of intervention. We must be vigilant to ensure that the
continuum is not abused, and we must be circumspect and as objective as
possible in examining evidence and placing a state on the continuum. However, I believe that almost all states can
be placed, with varying degrees of difficulty, on the continuum, and that this
placement will help us in determining proper state placement and intervention.
WORKS CITED
Corera, Gordon
“’Loose Nukes’ fear spurs US-Russia Action.” [Webpage and database]. BBC
News, 17MAR04. Available from <http://news.bbc.co.uk/go/pr/fr/-/2/hi/europe/4149153.stm>. Accessed 06JAN05.
Rashid, Ahmed “Musharraf’s Bin Laden Headache.”
[Webpage and database]. BBC News, World Edition, 17MAR04. Available from <http://news.bbc.co.uk/go/pr/fr/-/2/hi/south_asia/3545985.stm>. Accessed
06JAN05.
Rashid, Ahmed “Musharraf’s Power Play” [website and
database]. BBC News, World Edition, 12DEC04.
Available from <http://news.bbc.co.uk/go/pr/fr/-/2/hi/south_asia/4104655.stm.>. Accessed
06JAN05.
Scott-Joynt, Jeremy. “Terror Funding Brings Saudi
Mixed Messages” [website and database]. BBC
News, World Edition, 22JUL04. Available
from <http://news.bbc.co.uk/2/hi/business/ 3877755.stm>. Accessed 06JAN05.
Stephen D. Krasner,
“The Day After,” Foreign Policy,
January / February (2005), No. 146: 68-71.
Walzer, Michael. Just and Unjust Wars: A Moral Argument With
Historical Illustrations, 3rd ed.
“Washington Accuses
NOTES
[1] The views
expressed in this paper are those of the author and do not reflect the official
policy or position of the Department of the Army, Department of Defense, or the
U.S. Government.
[3]
Michael Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars: A
Moral Argument With Historical Illustrations, 3rd ed., (
[4] Ibid. 197
[5] Ibid. 197
[6] Ibid. 57
[7]
Ibid. 86
[8]
Ibid. 197
[9]
Jeremy Scott-Joynt, “Terror Funding Brings Saudi Mixed Messages” [website and
database] (BBC News, World Edition,
22JUL04); available from < http://news.bbc.co.uk/2/hi/business/3877755.stm>;
accessed 06JAN05.
[10]
“Washington Accuses
[11]
Ahmed Rashid “Musharraf’s Bin Laden Headache.” [webpage and database] (BBC News, World Edition, 17MAR04);
available from <: http://news.bbc.co.uk/go/pr/fr/-/2/hi/south_asia/3545985.stm>;
accessed 06JAN05.
[12]
Ahmed Rashid “Musharraf’s Power Play” [website and database] (BBC News, World Edition, 12DEC04);
available from <http://news.bbc.co.uk/go/pr/fr/-/2/hi/south_asia/4104655.stm.>;
accessed 06JAN05.
[13] Ahmed Rashid “Musharraf’s Bin Laden Headache.” [webpage and database] (BBC News, World Edition, 17MAR04); available from <: http://news.bbc.co.uk/go/pr/fr/-/2/hi/south_asia/3545985.stm>; accessed 06JAN05.
[14]
Gordon Corera “’Loose Nukes’ fear spurs US-Russia Action.” [webpage and
database] (BBC News, 17MAR04);
available from <http://news.bbc.co.uk/go/pr/fr/-/2/hi/europe/4149153.stm>;
accessed 06JAN05.