Ethics in Complex Contingencies:
New Demands on the Warrior Ethic
LTC Tony Pfaff
Prologue:
Soldiers searching for insurgents knocked
on an apartment door where they were told loyalists of Saddam Hussein were
hiding. They yelled out in English and Arabic “US Army, open the door!” After a
few minutes they heard a shot come from the apartment. In the confusion it was
not clear if it was aimed at them or not. The patrol leader, with little time
to react if he was to prevent the enemy from escaping or worse his men from
being injured or killed, decided to act. He ordered one of the soldiers to
break the door down and another to throw in a percussion grenade. After the
dust cleared, they found they had killed a teen-age girl and her father, who
fired the shot because he thought criminals were at the door.[1]
It is not the purpose of this paper to
second-guess hard decisions made by military professionals in the heat of
battle. However, situations like the one described above make the warrior
ethic, by which soldiers make and judge these decisions, seem inadequate. Given
the ethics of the military profession arguably these soldiers did nothing
wrong. Civilian deaths in war are legally and morally permissible. But what
troubles some about this example is that the family in question had survived
the major combat operations and was going about the business of reconstructing
their lives in post-Saddam
Introduction:
Situations like the ones described above are indicative that the increasing range of missions the Army is called upon to accomplish is stressing the warrior ethic and complicating its application in “real-world” environments. The warrior ethic evolved in the context of a Westphalian worldview where states have rights and can redress certain violations of those rights with military force. In this context, threats to those rights were other states and the military forces they employed. But today there is a mismatch between worldview and threat that is eroding the professional military ethic and this can have moral as well as practical implications. Shortly after the United States began conducting military operations in Afghanistan, an article appeared in the Los Angeles Times claiming that the military’s overwhelming concern for avoiding noncombatant casualties, driven largely by a desire to avoid domestic and international criticism, hampered its ability to accomplish its mission of finding Osama Bin Laden and ending the war quickly. Paradoxically, the article pointed out, this lengthened the war and led to more noncombatant deaths.[2]
What complicates matters is that the
military is confronting not only a wider range of threats, but with the
emergence of fourth-generation warfare, different kinds of threats as well.
Over the last decade, the military has been called upon to keep the peace in
Ethically speaking these operational
distinctions can be important. While the warrior ethic treats mission
accomplishment as a moral imperative, it also recognizes the moral and legal
limitations that shape our judgment regarding the conduct of military force.
These constraints call on members of the military to always strive to use the
least force necessary, whether fighting wars or keeping peace. However what is
necessary in war can be excessive in peace, and failure to recognize this can
have dire consequences. This means when transforming the military
profession, one must address not only its structure and organization, but its
ethics as well. To resolve the
confusion and prevent ethically—and politically—self-defeating applications of
force, we will need to extend the warrior ethic to account for the increasing range
and changing nature of the threat.
The most salient difference
between the use of force in peace and war, which I’ll label the enemy and
criminal models respectively, is the room each makes for civilian casualties.
In the enemy model, soldiers may act in such a way that noncombatants may be
harmed or even killed, but under the criminal model, police may not. In the
former, combatants have greater permissions to put noncombatants at risk while
in the latter; the protection police owe civilians is nearly absolute. [3] This difference, when applied in
the environment of complex contingencies, provides a significant challenge for
the military professional. In both models, the obligations owed noncombatants
and bystanders depend on the kind of threat soldiers are facing; but the nature
of the threat is not always clear and this has led to confusion, and in some
cases tragedy, as soldiers faithfully apply an ethic better suited for war in
conditions of peace and vice-versa.
To illustrate my point and hopefully resolve some of the moral
confusion, I will discuss first how the potential conflict between apparent
restrictions of the “police” ethic and the perceived obligations of the
“warrior” ethic create and produce moral confusion. This requires a discussion
of the sources of the professional military ethic as well as the civic peace
that members of the police and military forces are obligated to protect and the
distinct permissions, prohibitions, and obligations that bind on them when
doing so. The result gives us two models
of the ethics of force-- a “criminal” and a “enemy” ethic—from which we can
articulate distinct “police” and “warrior” ethics that define the ethical
environment in which members of the military find themselves and identify their
requisite obligations and permissions. This will require a discussion of the
threats faced by the state and how they have evolved in view of
fourth-generation warfare. The paper concludes by showing how this complexity
can be recognized and resolved by modifying and extending the jus in
Figure 1: Sources of the
Professional Military Ethic
The Professional Military Ethic:
The professional military ethic, which I
will treat as synonymous with the warrior ethic derives its substance primarily
from three sources: 1) functional imperatives of the profession; 2) national
values, beliefs and norms; and 3) international laws and treaties. While these
sources complement each other, they can also be a source of ethical tension.
The functional imperative obligates military professionals “to put the mission
first, refuse to accept defeat, (and) never quit…”[4] This
essentially utilitarian imperative,[5]
captured in the notions “military necessity,” obligates military professionals
to maximize the good by undertaking missions that will most likely lead to
victory and do everything in their power to accomplish them. The other
components, national values and beliefs as well as international law and
treaties, which philosopher Michael Walzer refers to collectively as the “war
convention,” are largely deontic[6]
constraints that give substance to what it means for military professionals to
execute their duties ethically. Since
utilitarian ethics seek to maximize some good—in this case victory—while deontic
ethics seek to uphold a principle regardless of the consequences, it is not
hard to see how conflicts can arise. But we cannot simply resolve the conflict
by prioritizing one over the other. Values, beliefs, and law can restrict the
means by which military professionals fulfill the obligations of the functional
imperative; however, violating them can undermine the domestic and
international political will necessary to sustain the fight. According to an
The Increasing
The war convention includes the range of articulated norms,
customs, professional codes, legal precepts, religious and philosophical
principles, and reciprocal arrangements that aim to prevent war, and failing
that, to limit the misery caused by war. This requires soldiers to subordinate
the use of force to the aim of establishing or preserving a just and stable
peace. [8] This convention
is more than a set of rules; it is but rather a framework that gives us the
range of reasons we can give to tell when wars are just, and what actions are
just when fighting them.
According to the war convention, war is permissible when the political
sovereignty (PS) and territorial integrity (TI) of a state is violated.[9] This defines an “act of aggression”
that warrants a military response. [10] It is
beyond the scope of this paper to give a complete account of why this is the
case, but roughly, the state has a moral obligation to preserve civic peace, [11] which is
necessary if citizens are going to enjoy the rights to life and liberty
specified in the Declaration of Independence and which the Constitution
requires members of the US military to defend. For the state to do this, it
must exercise political sovereignty over the territories in which its citizens
reside. This is an important
consideration as it allows us to distinguish enemies from criminals: enemies are capable of violating a state’s
rights; criminals are only capable of violating an individual’s rights.
In the face of an
enemy, military forces must secure a more stable peace than before hostilities
began, one in which the enemy is defeated. In the face of crime, law
enforcement professionals must aim at maintaining a state of civic peace that
allows citizens to go about their lives without fear of crime. [12]
In both cases, it must be the kind of peace in which conflicting parties can
and want to resolve their differences non-violently, which means parties in
conflict must have available to them peaceful means to resolve conflicts of
interest. This not only means that at the end of a war warring states must be
able to co-exist peacefully, but the citizens within each state must be able to
do so as well. This requires just and stable political and judicial systems. This
means the restoration of civic peace in
Establishing political stability is
dependent on the restoration of civic peace, which is the kind of peace
necessary to attain and secure fundamental human goods, including security and
distributive justice.[13] According
to political philosopher Mortimer Adler, civic peace is only possible in the
context of community. A necessary feature of a community is a government that
is capable of administering a process by which conflicts are resolved
non-violently. For this to be possible, members of the community must cede some
sovereignty to the community. This then gives us a set of conditions that
must be present if we are to say a state of peace holds:
1)
The enemy is defeated or transformed into a threat
not capable of violating PS or TI.
2)
Institutions necessary for law enforcement must be
functioning including police, courts, and prisons.[14]
3) These
institutions must be credible, that is people must be willing to rely on them
to resolve disputes.
When these conditions hold, the criminal model will apply. When they do not, the enemy model will be more appropriate. This is because the civic peace a society enjoys is fundamentally different than the state of peace that can exist between states. Independent states, says Adler, have not ceded sovereignty, are always in a state of potential war. This does not mean states cannot enter into arrangements in which non-violent conflict resolution is preferable. It just means that when a state’s rights to PS and TI are violated, the state may take matters into its own hands; however, when an individual’s rights to life and liberty are violated, he must rely on the state to restore them.
The following example serves to illustrate
the importance of this distinction. During a joint Marine-police operation
conducted during the 1992
This example is instructive because it shows that even in the same
situation there is a different understanding between police and members of the
military as to how much force is minimally necessary. Even though they
had been shot at, the police did not feel that they or anyone else were in
immediate danger. In their view it would be better to develop the situation and
ascertain if there were non-violent ways to resolve the issue. However, as far
as the Marines were concerned it would be morally appropriate to respond with
any degree of force that eliminated the threat even if it put civilians at some
risk. The different reactions are due to
the way each perceives the threat, and the way each is trained to deal with it.
For the police, the threat is a criminal they must apprehend in order to
minimize the disruption to the peace crime represents. Since the use of
violence represents a further disruption of the peace, police are always
looking to use the least force possible. But Marines are trained to
defeat enemies, who must be killed if there is to be peace. They are always
looking to use the most force permissible. In complex contingencies,
however, it is not always clear what kind of threat soldiers are facing.
In Bosnia, rather than defending the US ‘s
rights to PS and TI, the US military prevented rival militias from violating
the life and liberty of Bosnian citizens. In
To make matters more complex, in both
This diversity of threat, coupled with the
moral imperative to accomplish missions,[18]
dramatically complicates ethical decision-making. In fact, a Human Rights Watch
(HRW) report issued in October 2003 argued that Coalition forces in many cases
needed to conduct themselves more like law enforcement officials, but lacked
the capability and training. [19] But
the truth of such an observation is not intuitively obvious, at least not from
a soldier’s point of view. Combatants
are permitted to conduct operations in which noncombatants will be harmed;
however, at some point it is reasonable to ask, do foreign citizens have a
right to expect the kind of protection they would receive if the same kinds of
operations were conducted in the
The Changing Threat:
Fourth Generation Warfare
For it to be
permissible to harm noncombatants the acts that threaten the peace will have to
be more than mere crimes, they will have to be “acts of war.” This is an
important point because it suggests that while the current response to some
terrorists and insurgents may be justifiable, that may not always be the case.
Some are more like criminals and to pursue them as enemies risks doing more
moral harm than good.
What complicates
matters is the ability of anti-Coalition forces to conduct fourth generation,
or asymmetric, warfare which joint doctrine defines as attempts to circumvent
or undermine an opponent’s strength while exploiting his weaknesses using
methods that he either cannot or will not use.[20] This does not simply mean smaller forces can
defeat larger ones by exploiting unexpected weaknesses. It means small forces
can violate the political sovereignty and territorial integrity of a state
without the support of another state.[21]
Thus, the ability to wage fourth generation warfare suggests that some threats,
though they may be more organized like criminals, may be more appropriately
regarded as enemies. Before
In view of these
changes, the criminal and war models are inadequate to fully account for the
moral obligations, permissions, and prohibitions law enforcement officials and
members of the military have to innocents and noncombatants in the conduct of
complex contingencies. They are inadequate because the threats they are
designed to respond to are not the kind of threats represented by the
insurgents, terrorists, and criminals currently confronting the
|
War |
Peace |
Complex Contingencies |
Threat |
Enemies: threaten states’ political sovereignty and territorial integrity |
Criminals: threaten individuals’ life and liberty |
Enemies and Criminals coexist |
Obligations |
Defend nation while observing restrictions of war convention; may not intentionally harm noncombatant |
Must maintain peace; must use the least force possible to protect life and liberty; must not harm bystanders |
Must not harm bystanders; but must preserve political sovereignty and territorial integrity |
Permissions |
Use the most force permissible to establish peace given the war convention; may unintentionally, harm noncombatants |
May detain suspected criminals, may use armed force against violent criminals who represent continued threat |
May harm noncombatants only to prevent violation of political sovereignty and territorial integrity |
Table 1: Obligations,
Permissions, and Threats
Restraining the use of Force:
Noncombatant Immunity and Necessity
If the goal
of military force is to establish or maintain a just peace, it must be applied
in a just manner. However, as noted earlier, moral restrictions on force can
impede the military’s ability to fulfill its other obligations. It is a nearly
universally accepted moral principle that it is wrong to intentionally harm
innocent people. However, states are obligated to protect their citizens from
harm, but sometimes, military professionals and police must risk violating the
former principle in order to uphold the latter. Combatants sometimes must
attack enemy military targets located close to where noncombatants live. Police
sometimes must put bystanders’ lives at risk when they pursue criminals. The
application of these principles is further complicated by the fact combatants
may intentionally kill enemy soldiers—many of whom are not guilty of any act of
aggression.
International
law resolves some of this complexity by prohibiting combatants from
intentionally killing citizens of enemy states who are not directly involved in
the fighting, regardless of their innocence or guilt.[23] They
are immune from harm because they are not immediate threats to the
ability of military forces to prosecute the war. Because they do not represent an immediate threat,
their deaths are not necessary in order to achieve the goals of the
war. Thus in the context of fighting wars, the law
and morality of war typically distinguishes between noncombatants and
combatants as opposed to the innocent and guilty or civilians and soldiers.
This is because many combatants are innocent of any act of aggression and some
civilians are guilty of it. This is also
because some combatants, such as those who have surrendered or are wounded and
not capable of fighting, no longer represent a threat and are thus immune from
harm. Further, some civilians like munitions workers, because they are engaged
in an activity that is logically inseparable from war fighting when they are
working at the factory, are subject to harm.[24]
Since police do not typically fight wars, it may seem odd to discuss
noncombatant immunity in this context; but because they also deal with threats
to the peace, analogous notions apply. For police, only those civilians who
have somehow demonstrated themselves to be a violent threat may be killed. And
even then, police must make reasonable attempts to apprehend them first.[25]
Thus, in the context of the pursuit of criminals we can make a distinction
between 1) innocent civilians, who are not a violent threat and are not subject
to harm, and 2) suspects, who may have committed a crime, but who must be given
the opportunity to surrender first. In this latter category, police may only
use deadly force after they have offered the suspect a chance to surrender and
then only to prevent someone suspected of a violent crime from fleeing or
committing a violent crime. Typically, police do not use deadly force against
non-violent criminals.
Noncombatant Immunity and the Limits of Risk
Noncombatant immunity, as well as its
law-enforcement analog, obligates soldiers and police to take additional risks
in order to fulfill their respective functions. For the soldier this most often
means establishing peace between the society he serves and other societies; for
the police officer, this most often means detaining, and under certain
circumstances killing, someone who represents an immediate threat to the peace
the society currently enjoys.[26]
Inasmuch as this often involves the use of deadly force, they sometimes put
others at risk as well. Their functions, however, limit whom they may put at
risk and the kinds of risks they may take.
This is not to say that police are prohibited from taking some risks
that might place civilian lives in danger. For example, police are permitted
to engage in high-speed pursuits though such pursuits can result in accidents
where innocent bystanders are killed. But police are not permitted to engage in
such pursuits, or any other activity, if they know civilians will be
killed or seriously injured.[27] This means that police should seek to
use the least force possible, and never in such a way will an innocent be
harmed, as this would represent a breach of the peace their purpose is to
serve.
The risks soldiers may place on noncombatants are also limited, but in a
qualitatively different way. The deadly force that circumstances sometimes
force soldiers to employ is justified by the fact their role is to defend
innocents against aggression, thus fulfilling in part the moral obligation
states have to protect their citizens. But if the defense of innocents is a
moral imperative, then the intentional taking of innocent life must be
morally prohibited. Thus while soldiers have the positive duty to protect
their own civilians, they also have the negative moral duty not to
intentionally harm civilians of other nations.
However, to effectively protect their own civilians, soldiers must seek
to avoid risk. This is not simply prudential self-interest, but necessary if
they are to sustain the operations necessary to end the war. As a general rule
of thumb, the amount of long-range and indirect fire combatants can place on an
objective is inversely proportional to the resistance they experience in taking
it. For example, soldiers attempting to assault and urban area can greatly
reduce their risk by using artillery and close air support to reduce to rubble
buildings the enemy would use for cover. But, especially in densely populated
areas, this is almost certainly going to result in deaths of civilians.
While such tactics reduces the risk to the combatants, they are often
less discriminating and increase risk to noncombatants. However, by virtue of
accepting their role, combatants obligate themselves to accept risks that
noncombatants do not, regardless of the noncombatant’s nationality.[28] This
obligation, however, is limited to some degree by the sometimes-competing
obligation to accomplish missions that are necessary for combatants to protect
the citizens of their state. If there
were no such limits, then the ability of combatants to accomplish their
missions would be severely undermined, as it would be possible for the enemy to
use civilians as shields and render it impossible to prosecute the war in a
moral fashion.[29]
This would render the positive duty to defend innocent life illogical and
morally self-defeating. Thus, combatants are not obligated to take so much
risk that the mission will fail, nor are they obligated to take so much risk
that it is certain their unit will not be able to continue the war effort. [30]
Since the amount
of obligated risk is limited, it is then permissible for combatants to engage
in courses of action in which they may unintentionally, but knowingly, harm
civilians. But this too has its limits. Judgments about what constitutes the kinds
of risk that may lead to mission failure are notoriously difficult to make.
Thus if our ethical obligations ended at balancing risk to soldiers with risk
to noncombatants, the potential for abuse would fatally undermine the entire
concept of noncombatant immunity as even well-meaning soldiers would be hard
pressed to come up with reasons to take the safety of noncombatants into
account. This is the logic of the
soldiers in the opening example, who chose to employ weapons that could discriminate
between combatants and noncombatants in the manner and conditions in which the
soldiers employed them. This underscores the need for professionals who have
the education and experience required to maintain the profession’s integrity
and balance mission accomplishment with moral and legal restrictions. So while it makes sense to limit
principle-based constraints on military necessity in this manner, we also have
to recognize that these constraints are in tension and must be interpreted in
the context of particular situations.
Essential to understanding just conduct in war, or jus in
Fig 2: Force vs.
Risk
Fig 2: Force vs Risk: In this figure the black line illustrates the inverse force
vs. risk relationship that exists for police and military personnel. The
more force they use, roughly speaking, the less risk to themselves. The
solid black line represents the range of permissible uses of force under
both criminal and enemy models. When so much force is used that bystanders
would knowingly be harmed (marked by the yellow star) then increased use of
force is no longer permissible under the criminal model, represented by the
dashed line. When so much force is
used that it violates jus in The blue line illustrates the direct
relationship between the use of force by military and police personnel and
increased risk to noncombatants. The solid represents acceptable risk in
peace and war, the dashed line acceptable risk in war, and the dotted line
risk that is never acceptable. The arrows left of the intersection of the
two lines, marked by the yellow star, indicate that, in peace one should
only use the least force possible. The arrows to the right of the
intersection indicate that in war, one is permitted to use the most force
permissible
Application of Proportionality
and Discrimination in Complex Environments:
Proportionality and discrimination
require combatants not only to minimize the deaths of noncombatants, but also
to make a positive commitment to preserving noncombatant lives by not
exploiting the harm they do and assuming additional risk to minimize that harm in
the first place. However, application of these provisions in complex
contingencies is not clear and this has generated a great deal of discussion and
confusion as soldiers attempt to apply an ethic that evolved to deal with
enemies in environments where there may not be any.
According
to a Human Rights Watch Report, more than twenty civilians were killed in
“The individual cases of civilian deaths documented
in this report reveal a pattern by US forces of over-aggressive tactics,
indiscriminate shooting in residential areas and a quick reliance on lethal
force. In some cases, US forces faced a real threat, which gave them the right
to respond with force. But that response was sometimes disproportionate to the
threat or inadequately targeted, thereby harming civilians or putting them at
risk.”[33]
While some of this criticism may be justified, what the HRW report fails
to take into account is that much of what it criticizes is not prohibited by
the war convention. But in applying an ethic developed for war in environments
other-than-war, members of the military risk undermining what peace they may
have established as well as the moral purpose the major combat operations
served. While the transition from war to peace has always been a complicated
process, it is much more so for complex contingencies. The implications of
fourth generation warfare suggest that simply defeating Saddam’s conventional
forces has not ended the fight and that the participation of Islamic terrorists
suggest the consequences of losing risks far more than restoration of the
political sovereignty and territorial integrity of Iraq. Should
The HRW report argues that the problem Coalition forces have is
“attitudinal.” However, it is not the case that Coalition forces are not deeply
concerned about noncombatant deaths and it is the case they routinely take
actions to prevent them. The problem is better described as theoretical. Proportionality
and discrimination, even though they constrain military necessity would permit
harm to civilians. What is needed then is to modify our understanding of these
restraints in a way that incorporates the ethical restrictions of the criminal
model and provides a flexible, yet comprehensive moral framework for the
application of military force.
Proportionality:
On
Applied to the above examples, proportionality is upheld in terms of
civilian lives and property destroyed vs. enemy killed or captured, or
operations impeded. However, what is not measured is the cost to the fragile
peace the major combat operations achieved. This is because the law and
morality of war do not presume a peace. This
suggests that if one accepts that the conditions of peace hold, even if it is a
fragile peace, then the criminal model will be the most appropriate to apply. This would mean once the man brandishing the
gun in the first example above was incapacitated to the point it was possible
to detain him the morally appropriate response was to arrest, not kill,
him.
However, simply telling soldiers to behave more like police—which is
appropriate in most peacekeeping situations—ignores the complex environment of
the GWOT. By hiding among civilians, insurgents can avoid harm and thus
continue their own operations since even with precision weapons some
noncombatants will be harmed. This poses a serious problem in the context of
fourth generation warfare. Cell phones and other means of communication can be
easily replaced. Weapons and explosives are plentiful in
Therefore, one must not fall into the trap
of calculating it in terms of noncombatant lives lost versus enemy lives taken.
To the extent enemy activity itself represents a threat to the restoration of
sovereignty, permissions associated with noncombatant casualties are going to
be greater. In this case what matters is how much closer any particular
operation will bring one to eliminating the threat. If certain key leaders are
the essential to insurgents’ ability to conduct operations, then military
leaders may need to consider this when determining how best to pursue them. In
this kind of warfare, the number of civilian lives lost and property destroyed
needs to measure against how much harm the targeted insurgent could do.
But this does not mean such permissions
will be unlimited. If the insurgent target in question is relatively
inconsequential, then proportionality requires US forces to forego engaging
them. Thus, in the environment of complex contingencies, proportionality should
be modified in the following way:
The harm to
noncombatants and their property must be proportional to the desired military
objective and measured against the threat to political sovereignty and
territorial integrity; however, when the establishing a stable peace is no longer at risk, the bad effect
must be measured against the threat individual life and liberty.
This also suggests is that military forces need to develop non-lethal
means of dealing with the insurgent threat. This means not only should military
forces be trained in law-enforcement techniques but they should also have
available to them non-lethal weapons in order to lower the cost to lives and
property of conducting counter-insurgent operations.
Discrimination of targets:
As noted earlier,
it is morally self-defeating to intentionally kill noncombatants. For this
reason, combatants must discriminate between enemy combatants who represent a
threat and noncombatants who do not. Thus while combatants may engage in
courses of action in which noncombatants may be killed, they cannot intend
those deaths to occur. However, in
complex contingencies, not only can it be difficult to distinguish combatant
from noncombatant, it is also difficult to distinguish if harm to noncombatants
will be permissible. This requires two levels of discrimination: 1) between
targets and 2) acceptable risk to noncombatants and bystanders. If the threat is an enemy, in the
technical sense discussed above, then some harm will be permissible as long as
it is also proportional. If the threat is a criminal, then some risk of harm will be acceptable as long
as it too is proportional. In the former, soldiers may foresee, but not intend
the harm. In the latter, they may foresee, but not intend the risk.
The following example serves to
illustrate the importance of this distinction. On 7 August,
In
the above examples, the deaths of noncombatants were certainly unintended –the
soldiers manning the checkpoints were simply dealing with a threatening
situation in accordance with their rules of engagement. Given the nature of combat
at the time, there was no way, in principle, for the soldiers to tell if the
individuals in the cars were civilians or Saddam’s Fedayeen. But if one
accepted that the conditions of peace hold, then noncombatant deaths must not
only be unintended, they may not knowingly be permitted. This means
soldiers must take extra precautions to ensure risks to civilians is minimized
by, for example, marking checkpoints (in this case) and ensuring warnings are
heard and that soldiers are trained and capable of employing alternate
nonviolent means to stop suspected insurgents and criminals.
Thus
in complex contingencies, the jus in
In addition to discerning whether it is permissible to engage a
particular target, soldiers must also discern whether it is permissible to risk
harm to civilians when doing so. During operations in
In
While
it is certainly permissible to fire on a gunman shooting at you or destroy
facilities used by insurgents, even if they are not in them at the time, placing civilians in harm’s way to “send
messages” to intimidate the populace would violate soldiers’ obligations to
discriminate in terms of targets as well as harms. However, it is important to note that when
insurgents use populated areas as cover for their operations, they put
civilians at risk and thus bear at least some responsibility for any harm.
Further, to the extent civilians consent to insurgent operations, even if they
are not active participants, they too bear some responsibility for this risk.
This does not diminish the responsibility members of the military to avoid,
much less intend, harm to noncombatants and bystanders; however, it does beg
the question what permissions the military has, especially if the war model
applies.[40]
If the insurgent threat is capable of conducting war, then targeting their
facilities is permissible, even if it intimidates the local populace. However,
if the conditions of peace hold, then such tactics will more likely threaten
life and liberty and disrupt the peace rather than maintain it. In this case,
such tactics should be prohibited. Under the war model, targeting the enemy
and enemy facilities is permissible, regardless of whether it
intimidates the population. Under the criminal model, targeting criminals and
their facilities is permissible unless it intimidates the local population,
who presumably have a right to the civic peace such intimidation violates.
Policy Implications:
Several policy implications follow from the above discussion.
1. Military professionals, Just War
theorists, international lawyers, as well as others who rely on the various
provisions of the war convention to form policy and law, need to apply the war
and criminal models to extend theory and law to complex operations that involve
multiple threats, which differ not only in capability, but also in kind.
2. Tactical and operational doctrine
needs to be modified to acknowledge and describe the difference between
criminal and enemy threats and then develop tactics, techniques and procedures
to handle each.
3. In complex contingencies, the
language of operations orders and rules of engagement must reflect the ethical
demands of the environment. This would mean finding language that specifies if
a particular operation, or parts of an operation, permit using the most force
permissible or the least force possible or whether civilian casualties are
permitted.
4. Develop and educate forces that are
trained in law enforcement procedures and provide them with non-lethal weapons
so soldiers have a wider range of options for applying the least force
possible. This may include reconsidering whether certain weapons and ammunition
currently not permitted for soldiers’ use, such as CS gas and “dum dum”
bullets, should be permitted. Though they can have undesired effects, they too,
give the soldiers a wider range of options for applying the least force
possible.
5. Increase inter-operability training
with civilian government and non-governmental organizations to increase the
range of non-violent options available.
Conclusion:
US operations over
the last decade are filled with stories of where Coalition forces restrained
the use of force in order to preserve civilian lives, even when the law and
morality of war did not require it. This author does not question the
commitment of the military, as an institution, to upholding the principle of
noncombatant immunity. However, what is lacking is a conceptual framework that
accounts for how to apply the principle in the wide variety of environments
members of the military find themselves—often within the scope of a single
operation. This is necessary if we are to have consistency in the face of this
complexity.
What also follows from this discussion is
that it will not always be clear what threat soldiers are facing, which means
it will be up to military professionals to rely on their experience and
judgment to discern which approach, criminal or enemy, is appropriate to apply.
This underscores the need for a
professional education curriculum that accounts for the demands of both models.
Further, while the discussion of proportionality and discrimination was
meant to suggest the kinds of obligations, permissions and prohibitions that
exist regarding the use of military force in complex contingencies, it is by no
means complete. The restoration of civic peace is not only a job for the
military and more work needs to be done to build a comprehensive approach that
draws on the professional resources and experience of civilian institutions which
are necessary for creating the conditions for civic peace.
Some may argue that placing such
constraints on fighting a deadly enemy needlessly and irresponsibly restrains
soldiers from pursuing courses of action that allow them to effectively to
protect themselves, as well as the civilians they are sworn to defend. But it
is also true that prosecuting a war in a way that violates our own values risks
undermining the political will necessary to successfully see the war to a
successful end. Coalition forces should pursue an aggressive policy by which
they engage insurgents and terrorists wherever and whenever they find them. But
they must also must recognize when violations of individuals’ right to life and
liberty is not permissible and restrain the use of force accordingly.
This requires policies and procedures that
recognize necessity must be constrained and interpreted in different ways,
depending on the situation in which it is applied. In some cases it means using
the most force permissible, given the restrictions of proportionality and
discrimination. In others, it means using the least possible and never in such
a way that civilians are knowingly put at risk. Furthermore, even if in
particular situations conforming to moral obligations leads to restraint and
perhaps missed opportunities, this may be the short-term price to pay in order
to gain the long-term benefit maintaining the moral high-ground brings.[41]
NOTES
[1] Adapted from “Hearts and Minds: Post-war Civilian Deaths in Baghdad Caused by U.S. Forces,” Human Rights Watch, vol15, no 9(E) October 2003, p. 26-29.
[2] William
Arkin, Fear of Civilian Deaths May Have
Undermined Effort,
[3] Tony
Pfaff, Peacekeeping and the Just War
Tradition,
[4] http://www-tradoc.army.mil/pao/web_specials/warriorthos/.
See also: USMA Circular: 1-101: Cadet Leader Development System, June 2002,
United States Military Academy,
[5] Utilitarian ethics seek to maximize some good while minimizing some evil. In the context of military operations, victory in a just war presumably maximizes the good. Since victory maximizes the good, members of the military have an obligation to conduct operations that will lead to that victory and conduct them in such a way that will maximize the chances victory.
[6] Deontic ethics seek to describe those principles which must be followed regardless of the consequences.
[7] CBS News
Poll,
[8] Michael
Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars,
[9] Ibid.
[10] Walzer, ch 4. There are a number of “aggressive acts” that fall short of warranting war such as raising tariffs, breaking a treaty, harassing one’s citizens abroad, etc. For the purpose of this paper, “acts of aggression” will exclusively refer to acts that violate political sovereignty and territorial integrity.
[11] States are obligated to maintain peace and protect citizens from harm. This obligation arises from the belief that all persons have a right to life and liberty. While it is beyond the scope of this paper to argue this point, it does entail if persons have such rights, then someone has an obligation to guarantee them. In the case, this obligation falls to the state.
[12] Walzer, p. 121 what justifies the use of force in both contexts is to correct or prevent an injustice and it is presumed the state of affairs that leads to injustice is unstable. Thus if force only returns the state of affairs to its original state it has served no moral purpose.
[13] Adler,
Mortimer, How to Think About War and Peace,
[14] Adler, p. 65-66.
[15] James
D. Delk, Fires & Furies: The LA Riots, Palm Springs: ETC
Publications, 1995. Quoted in Christopher M. Schnaubelt, “Lessons in Command
and Control from the
[16] Dana
Priest, “
[17] Michael
Hirsh, “Blood and Honor,” Newsweek,
[18] If the state has a moral obligation to protect its citizens, then members of the military have a prima facie moral obligation to attempt to fulfill all orders that are not morally prohibited to serve that end.
[19] “Hearts and Minds,” p. 7-9.
[20] Roger
Barnett, Asymmetrical Warfare, (Brassey’s Inc:
[21] A stark example of this, of course, is
[22] Tony Pfaff, “Noncombatant Immunity and the War on Terror” unpublished presentation at the Joint Services Conference on Professional Ethics, January 2003. http://www.usafa.edu/isme/JSCOPE03/Pfaff03.html
[23] 1923 Hague Rules of Aerial Warfare, Article 22, 1949 Geneva Convention IV, Article 3.
[24] Walzer, p. 138-175.
[25] John
Kleinig, The Ethics of Policing,
[26] Pfaff, p. 17-18
[27] Kleinig, pp. 118-122. See also Pfaff, 13-20.
[28] James M. Dubik, “Human Rights, Command Responsibility, and Walzer’s Just War Theory,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 11, no. 4 (1982): 355.
[29] This
has been, in fact, a feature of the Taliban strategy against the
[30] Paul
Christopher, The Ethics of War and Peace:
An Introduction to Legal and Moral Issues, 2nd ed.,
[31] Richard
Norman, Ethics, Killing and War,
[32] Walzer points out that destroying infrastructure, such as that related to the production of food and potable water, may also lead to civilian deaths and thus must be avoided. Michael Walzer, Arguing About War, New Haven Conn, Yale University Press, 2004 p. 94-98
[33] Hearts and Minds, p. 4.
[34] Frontline: “Truth, War, and Consequences,” produced by Martin Smith. http://www.pbs.org/wgbh/pages/frontline/shows/truth/etc/anger.html
[35] Hearts and Minds, 26-29.
[36] Hearts and Minds, p .18-23
[37] David Fastabend, “The Categorization of Conflict,” Parameters, Summer (1997): 75. http://carlisle-www.army.mil/usawc/Parameters/97summer/fastaben.htm
[38]Karon, Hemdawi
[39] Hendawi
[40] Theodore Koontz, “Noncombatant Immunity in Michael Walzer’s Just and Unjust Wars,” Ethics and International Affairs, Vol II, 1997, p. 79-80.
[41] I am
grateful for the help of my colleagues Dr PJ Ivanhoe, Major Joe Rank, Mr
Charley Metcalf, Ms Lorelei Kelly, Dr Jean-Marie Arrilligo, Ms Traci
Canterbury, and Ms