Countervalue Nuclear Warfare:
The Limit Case of Noncombatant
Immunity
by Lieutenant Colonel
John Mark Mattox, US Army
Imagine a
weapon of such destructive power that, in one instant, it totally devastates
five square miles, kills 70 thousand people, and injures 70 thousand
others. Imagine that, five months later,
an additional 70 thousand have died from the weapon’s effects and that five
years later, an additional 60 thousand have died—200 thousand in all[1]—virtually
all of whom are noncombatants.
What you
have just imagined is not imaginary; it is the actual result of the bombing of
·
What reasons can be offered to
justify a countervalue bombing strategy of the kind employed at
·
How satisfactory are those
reasons?
Finally,
and more generally,
·
Is it possible in human affairs
for circumstances to become so bad that the wholesale killing of noncombatants
becomes morally justifiable?
In the remarks that follow, I propose to consider these questions.
Countervalue versus Counterforce
Before continuing,
however, it is worth pausing to distinguish between the two general bombing
strategies of the 20th century:
countervalue and counterforce. A
“counterforce” strategy is one that targets enemy military forces; whereas, a “countervalue” strategy is one that targets
things upon which the enemy is likely to place a high “value.” As a practical
matter, countervalue targets could include, among other things, enemy civilian
population centers, or at least places with high concentrations of
noncombatants.
From a
strictly military standpoint, planners prefer counterforce strategies over
countervalue ones because counterforce strategies focus upon those targets that
can inflict the greatest harm upon friendly military forces. Moreover, from both the moral-philosophical
and legal standpoint, counterforce strategies are desirable because they
minimize problems associated with noncombatant immunity. However, the bombing of
President Truman makes this claim in unmistakably clear terms in his ex
post-facto justification of the attack: “It [the dropping of the atomic bomb]
was done to save 125,000 youngsters on the American side and 125,000 on the
Japanese side from getting killed and that is what it did. It probably also saved a half million
youngsters on both sides from being maimed for life. . . . I knew what I was
doing when I stopped the war that would have killed a half million youngsters
on both sides if those bombs had not been dropped. I have no regrets and, under the same
circumstances, I would do it again.”[2]
Now, many have expended endless energy over the years quibbling with the
President’s math.[3] However, as moral philosophers,
we have the luxury of accepting the President’s numbers at face value and
merely following the logical trail to see where it leads. Basically, the President presents a constructive
dilemma:
P1. Either invade the Japanese mainland,
P2. Or drop the bomb.
Then, in classic
utilitarian manner (i.e., selecting which horn of the dilemma will yield the
greatest happiness to the greatest number—greatest happiness being understood
as the greatest balance of pleasure and the least balance of pain for all
involved, each person counting as one and not more than one), the argument
continues:
P3. Invading the Japanese mainland will not yield the result required by
the
Greatest Happiness Principle.
Thus, by Truman’s logic, the inescapable
conclusion obtains:
C.
Therefore, drop the bomb.
However, the astute student of elementary logic will recognize that we
are not done, for the argument begs a critical question: “Is President
Truman’s dilemma a false
dilemma”? That is to say, are there
other reasonable alternatives to invading the Japanese mainland that could have
obviated the supposed logical necessity to drop the bomb? This, incidentally, is a question of more
than mere historical value, because the first question that every nuclear
policy planner has been called upon to answer since 1945 is, “What are the
alternatives to using a nuclear weapon”?
Let us, therefore, consider this question as it pertains specifically to
President Truman’s argument.[4]
Alternatives to the Countervalue Strategy
The historical record suggests at least four alternatives in addition to
the one mentioned in Truman’s dilemma—each of which Truman appears to have
ruled out. They were:
1.
to pursue Japanese “peace feelers”
sent through intermediaries,
2.
to await Soviet entry into the
war, a Soviet declaration of war, or at least a public declaration by the
Soviets of their intent to enter the war;
3.
to redefine “unconditional
surrender” to mean that the Allies would guarantee the continuation of the
Japanese Imperial institution;
4.
to provide a “warning” or
“non-combat” demonstration of the bomb;
and then a fifth alternative
which appears not to have been considered at length at the
time, but which we shall add for the
sake of completeness:
5.
to rely on the efficacy of
continued conventional warfare without actually invading the Japanese mainland.
Let us consider each alternative in turn, keeping in mind the concern for
noncombatant casualties.
Alternative 1. Prima facie, to pursue “peace
feelers” is an alternative that accords with most western sensibilities
concerning the just conduct of war.
Despite Augustine’s warning that, although all men want peace, they all
want it on their own terms,[5] the pursuit of peace is ostensibly a good thing. However, reasons for rejecting this
alternative appear to have included the fact that many of the “peace feelers”
were diplomatic messages sent through the Soviets, whose regime hardly was one
whose mediation could be looked upon with other than a jaundiced eye. Of equal concern was that the Japanese peace
feelers were conditional and vague—seeking a peace that (with no surprise to
Augustine) would maintain
Alternative 2. The logic of international politics seems to
hold that the more nations that assent to a military action, the more morally
justifiable the action must be. Thus, in
addition to sending a strong political signal to the Japanese, having the
Soviets along side in the fight against
Alternative
3. Merely dropping the demand for an
“unconditional surrender” by conceding the right of the Japanese imperial
institution to continue (which is, of course, what actually happened after the
bombing) has a seductively elegant quality to it. After all, just war theory generally eschews
the idea of surrenders being “unconditional.”[7] It seems plausible that accepting conditions
could have brought the conflict to a speedy and negotiated conclusion. However, there is also the political reality
that a belated change in surrender terms may have sounded like doublespeak to
the voters and veterans who had sacrificed much to achieve an unconditional
surrender. Moreover, it always must be
borne in mind that political symbols are specific to culture and context and
may not transfer readily across those boundaries. Thus, while American negotiators may have
considered proffers of peace to be magnanimous, the Japanese warlords might
just as easily have interpreted those proffers as a sign of weakening Allied
resolve and invigorated them to fight harder.
Alternative
4. Successful pursuit of this
alternative would have meant that noncombatant casualties could have been
avoided altogether. However, it is an
alternative fraught with practical problems of the kind that philosophers might
not wish to deal with, but which were of critical importance in 1945: the device may not have worked; the United
States had only enough nuclear materials for a very limited number of bombs;
and a suitable demonstration site may have been too remote to impress the
adversary. Moreover, we should note that
an advertised demonstration—as this would have to have been—would have invited
the Japanese to move Allied prisoners of war into the demonstration area as
human shields.
Alternative
5. Continuing the status quo—that
is, continuing to prosecute a conventional war in the Pacific—would have, by
definition, resolved the problems associated with nuclear weapons use. However, it would have highlighted other
issues (i.e., the open-ended continuation of the war, continued loss of
American lives, etc.), the concerns over which were, in the first instance,
among the very reasons for considering a nuclear alternative. Indeed, in addition to the political problems
associated with continued conventional action, it is not clear that this
alternative either would have curtailed the length of the war or lessened the
overall loss of human lives—combatant and noncombatant. True, the theory of
just war leads one to conclude that, all things being equal, the sacrifice of a
combatant’s life is to be preferred to the sacrifice of a noncombatant’s
life. However, what if the sacrifice of
one noncombatant life could result in saving two, or three or five, combatant
lives? After all, the Greatest Happiness
Principle upon which Truman’s reasoning appears to be founded does not
distinguish between combatants and noncombatants. Rather, it accords all human beings equal
weight in the calculation.
We
also might profitably consider now why the other horn of Truman’s
dilemma—namely, a conventional invasion of the Japanese mainland—might have
been unsatisfactory in the present context.
An invasion also would have resolved the problems associated with
nuclear weapons use. However, it would
not necessarily have resolved the problems associated with noncombatancy. The view was widely held that an attack on
the Japanese mainland would not merely have demoralized the civilian population
but, rather, would have transformed the entire population into de facto combatants.[8] The claim is not so far fetched; who cannot
imagine that if, for example,
Contemporary
Alternatives
It may be easy for us, as it
sometimes is for students of moral philosophy residing in the lofty realm of
ideas, to find ourselves put off by claims to the effect that some of the
alternatives available to Truman had to be rejected on the basis of political
concerns, such as: how the solutions
involved would play to the press or public, how much money the solutions would
cost, or how they might place the United States at some strategic disadvantage
in the international community. Should
moral philosophers be leery of such justifications? Probably so, especially if one holds that
moral considerations trump all others.
On the other hand, fair-minded people surely can conclude that none of
the alternatives to a countervalue nuclear strategy at
Suppose we, in 2004, found
ourselves in the shoes of President Truman.
Consider now, in a contemporary context, the five alternatives proposed
to Truman’s dilemma:
Alternative
1. How does
a nation sue for peace with a rogue state or non-state actor that, for example,
has weapons of mass destruction (WMD), is able to wreak disproportionately
great havoc with those weapons and produce large numbers of noncombatant
casualties, may threaten WMD use for ideological reasons, may have few targets
that can be held “at risk” such that the traditional theory of deterrence
cannot be brought to bear, and that—worst of all—may have no desire to sue for
peace?
Alternative
2. A nation might seek to marshal
public opinion in support of a conventional military strategy through
the framework of some existing alliance (like NATO) or under the auspices of
the United Nations. However, as is not
infrequently the case, some nations may not consider
military action to be the preferred solution.
Indeed, as we have witnessed recently, the best collective action
possible may be a “coalition of the willing.”
One might ask, “What’s wrong with coalitions of the willing”? In principle, nothing is wrong with them,
but making them work is by no means a simple task. In any case, the point may be moot: it is not clear that the moral status of an
action is affected by whether the action is taken unilaterally or multilaterally.
Alternative
3. The same problems apply today as
applied in 1945: one nation’s attempts at magnanimity may be interpreted by
another nation—particularly one led by a non-democratic regime—as sure evidence
of weakening resolve. By choosing this
alternative, whatever value the theory of nuclear deterrence would have held against
that regime might be lost, because deterrence requires that an adversary
perceive the deterring nation to possess unquestionably the resolve to act.
Alternative 4. For better or for worse, the
Alternative
5. A strictly conventional
response to a contemporary crisis of the magnitude of World War II in the
Pacific would, of course, solve the problem of whether to employ a countervalue
nuclear strategy. However, a unilateral
decision not to use nuclear weapons does not imply any guarantee that an
adversary, seeking to wreak disproportionate damage, would not, for example,
use WMD on the
What if an ideologically
motivated adversary could be deterred in no other way than by threat of the
countervalue use of nuclear weapons? One
is reminded of the words of an irritated President
Truman to the Federal Council of Churches a scant five days after the bombing
of Hiroshima and two days after the bombing of Nagasaki: “Nobody is more disturbed over the use of
Atomic bombs than I am but I was greatly disturbed over the unwarranted attack
by the Japanese on Pearl Harbor and their murder of our prisoners of war. The only language they seem to understand is
the one we have been using to bombard them.
When you have to deal with a beast you have to treat him as a
beast. It is most regrettable but
nevertheless true.”[9]
What does all of this imply for
President Truman’s decision to bomb
As pertaining to President
Truman, we can conclude that:
1.
either
Truman considered neither the concern for noncombatant casualties nor any of
the alternatives we have reviewed to afford sufficiently compelling arguments
to reject a countervalue nuclear strategy,
2.
or else he elected, in the face
of some better alternative, to opt for a countervalue nuclear strategy and thus
made what his own utilitarian logic would reveal to be a deeply flawed moral
choice.
If the latter is true, there is no vexing moral problem; Truman simply
made the wrong choice and there is nothing to discuss. However, if the former is true, and Truman
was right, then our examination of what we have called the “limit case” of
noncombatant immunity presents us with some challenging conclusions that go
right to the heart of our present inquiry:
1.
It may be that the concern over
noncombatant immunity does not trump
all other considerations. That is to
say, it may not necessarily be the case that the deliberate taking of
noncombatant lives is always to be avoided at all costs. On the contrary, assuming the historical
accuracy of the various alternatives we have reviewed, there may be imaginable
circumstances in which countervalue targeting (nuclear or otherwise) is the
most morally appropriate of available alternatives.
2.
Having so said, still it is the
case that, if the concern for noncombatant immunity can be overridden, the
threshold at which it can be overridden is not altogether clear. At least one can say that the burden of proof
in support of the proposition that countervalue targeting is circumstantially
the most morally appropriate alternative is substantial indeed. For example, would the burden be met with the
assertion that a countervalue strategy will shorten a war and thereby diminish
casualties on both sides?
3.
Finally, it could be argued that
although Truman was justified on utilitarian grounds, there may be other, more
appropriate grounds on which to explore questions of noncombatant immunity. Indeed,
it may be that no consequentialist moral framework ever will capture adequately
such considerations as the sanctity of human life.
As much as
we may wish to relegate to the past the discussion of things nuclear, we do not
enjoy the luxury to do so. Alternatives
not unlike the ones President Truman faced might be presented again to us and
to those to whom we are called upon to offer sound military advice informed
with a clear sense of moral conviction.
In the meantime, we would do well to recognize what is—thankfully—one of
only two cases of actual nuclear weapons use for its value as a limit case
study of the always perplexing problem of noncombatant immunity.
NOTES
[1] F. G. Gosling, The
[2] Harry S.
Truman, unsent letter dated
[3] See, for example, Gar Alperovitz, The Decision to Use the Atomic
Bomb (New York: Vintage Books,
1996): 515-521.
[4] Let us observe that a fruitful field of inquiry for 20th
century historiographers involves questions not only about Truman’s math, but
also about precisely what he and his associates knew at the time, how accurate
or honest the projected casualty figures were for an American invasion of
Japan, etc. Here again we can invoke
philosophical privilege and consider an array of plausible alternatives without
bogging down into questions of the precise historical role that those
alternatives played in the President’s decision-making process, and the
relative weight that he accorded to each.
In that way, we might hope to discover something of importance relative
to the larger question of how one justifies a countervalue nuclear strategy
that inevitably produces a significant number of noncombatant deaths.
[5] Augustine, City of
[6] “For Immediate Release to the Press, Radio and Television,” (Harry
S Truman to Tsukasa Nitoguri; Hiroshima File, Box 12, Post-Presidential
Secretary’s Office Files, Harry S Truman Library, quoted in Alperovitz 1996:
565.
[7] As the notion of “unconditional surrender” applies to the present
case, see, for example Michael Walzer, Just
and Unjust Wars, 2d ed. (Basic Books, 1977): 266, 267.
[8] See, for example, Walzer, 266, and United States Strategic Bombing Summary Report (Pacific War)
(Washington: GPO, 1 July 1946): 21.
Available online at http://www.anesi@anesi.com. Accessed
[9] Harry S Truman to Samuel McCrea Cavert,
[10] Beatrice Heuser, The Bomb:
Nuclear Weapons in their Historical, Strategic and Ethical Context (
[11]