“Five Degrees of Separation: A Plan
for Non-Combatant Protection”
JSCOPE 2004
Dr. Pauline Kaurin
DRAFT
Introduction
One of the greatest contemporary challenges to the
traditional combatant/non-combatant distinction is the question of
practicality: in warfare that is not strictly conventional, where it is not
clear whom the combatants are, where the non-combatants may appear hostile and
the combatants may try to hide in non-combatant populations, how do soldiers
determine who is a combatant (and a legitimate target) and who is a
non-combatant (and not a legitimate target)?
In a previous paper “Innocence Lost: The Future of the Combatant/Non-Combatant
Distinction” I made both moral and practical arguments for a five level
distinction to expand the current two level distinction. The basic line of argument (which I will
recap in the first section of paper) is that since there are multiple ways in
which one can be a combatant and multiple ways that one can be a non-combatant,
a distinction that takes account of this fact is morally necessary and
practically more likely to be implemented and observed on the ground.
In this paper I want to more fully
develop what exactly this five level distinction would look like, in what each
level would specifically consist and how each level might be implemented in
various kinds of situations, including ‘traditional’ combat, guerilla combat,
peacekeeping and humanitarian scenarios.
The aim of this second paper is to develop the five level distinction in
some detail and show how it could be applied in ways that would answer
objections that such a model would be impractical, too hard to teach/learn, or
would erode the moral intentions that now support the traditional distinction.
I.
Before
laying out the details of the five-part distinction, it will be important to
discuss the basic line of argument in favor of a multi-part distinction, as
opposed to the traditional two part combatant and non-combatant distinction.[1] What is it about combatants that justify them
being the object of violence? What is it about noncombatants that does not
justify the use of violence? The most
accessible fact about warfare seems to be the power differential between
combatants and non-combatants: some are armed and have a great deal of ability
to be a threat to others; some, not armed, are vulnerable to those who
are. Looking to Michael Walzer’s view,
we see that combatants are dangerous individuals; they carry weapons, they
can/will inflict this harm on others.[2] They are dangerous because they can inflict
harm and put others in dangerous situations; they can cause others to have
their rights violated, especially their right to life, but also the right to
autonomy or non-interference with their livelihood. In short, they have a
certain kind of power – an ability to be a threat, to be dangerous.
It is this core intuition that will
provide the foundation for both the moral and practical arguments for an
expanded combatant/non-combatant distinction. There must be something different
about the actions of the persons in the category that justify different
treatment; there are not just different administrative categories, but there
are different categories of actions – multiple ways to be/act like a combatant
and multiple ways to be/act like a noncombatant. First, there is a requirement of reason that one treat like cases alike
for the sake of logical consistency. If
there are persons who by virtue of their gender, age or social function would
normally be considered “non-combatants,” who are acting in a hostile,
threatening manner or causing harm, it would seem to be illogical to argue that
they should be treated in the same fashion as others who are not acting in that
fashion, who are not evincing threats or hostility.
However, it also seems illogical to
lump those “hostile” or threatening “non-combatants” as being worthy of the
same treatment as those who are clearly identified as “combatants,” who
threaten openly by visible signs (carrying a weapon, wearing a uniform with
fixed visible signs etc.) and have the advantages and protections of a military
or para-military structure. It would be
a category mistake not to make more fine-grained distinction as to how these
individuals are to be treated, if there are fine grained-differences between
how these individuals act and the effect that they can have on others.
Additionally, it is a requirement of justice
to treat like cases in a like manner and that either morally or legally
speaking it is unjust to treat like cases in a different manner, unless there
is a compelling reason to do so. Here it
is possible to raise concerns about undue partiality: How are we applying the
standards of justice in this case? What
is the rationale for its application? Given this application, how will future
cases be handled?[3]
In order to fairly and justly
accommodate analogous nuances within warfare, we will need more than the two
traditional categories. At a minimum the
two traditional categories will be necessary, but also categories for
unconventional belligerents and a category for “non-combatants” that might pose
some threat. Such an expanded
distinction would allow for a kind of flexibility that is required both by
considerations of logical consistency and justice, but a flexibility which is
not ad hoc or unduly partial. This distinction is further supported by the
intuition that there is “something about that person” that requires different
treatment – even if they are both non-combatants – and tries to articulate and
classify what that “something” looks like.
Secondly, a multi-part distinction
accords better with both classical and contemporary Just War theory, in
particular the jus in bello considerations
of discrimination and proportionality.
The principle of discrimination (or non-combatant immunity) calls for
soldiers to distinguish between those who are legitimate targets and those who
are not, refraining from attacking those who are not legitimate targets. The rationale for the immunity of
non-combatants is tied to the idea that these persons have rights that cannot
be violated, even for a legitimate military purpose. Take the case of munitions workers (who are
often in that ‘gray’ area between combatant and non-combatant): according to
Walzer they can only be attacked “…when they are actually engaged in activities
threatening and harmful to their enemies….We call them innocent people...which
means they have done nothing, are doing nothing which entails a loss of their rights.”[4]
Even though Walzer makes the
distinction a matter of rights, the rights are rooted in whether the actions of
the people in question warrant having their rights violated. A multi-part distinction maintains that there
are crucial differences between combatants and non-combatants, but also
recognizes that there are important differences – largely in terms of power and
vulnerability – within these categories as well. If there are these differences within the categories,
then it also follows that there are different types of rights within these
categories that ought to be taken seriously.
Failure to recognize and accommodate this fact could mean that the
traditional two-part distinction (in attempt to preserve the rights of the
corresponding two groups) ends up violating the rights of the other groups,
i.e. hostile non-combatants or unconventional belligerents.
An expanded distinction also accords
better with the principle of proportionality.
The idea of proportionality has played a central role in the Just War
tradition both in its own right, and also in connection with the idea of
self-defense.[5] If one uses more force than is necessary to
achieve the end, one is inflicting unnecessary (and therefore unjustified)
suffering which could in turn endanger the possibility of restoring a lasting
peace after the conflict has ended. The
traditional distinction generally recognizes two categories of force as
legitimate: against combatants lethal force is justified, but against
non-combatants lethal force is not justified, and further they are entitled to
protection from force. Therefore, it is
possible that having only two categories ends up inflicting more harm than
necessary to achieve the end. An
expanded distinction, on the other hand, is able to recognize gradations of
power, danger and threat within the categories of combatant and non-combatant
and can require that one use only enough force to stop or deal with that
threat, thereby avoiding the infliction of unnecessary suffering. With an expanded distinction the question
becomes “How much force is necessary to deal with this threat?” rather than the
question “Is the use of force (usually lethal) justified or does this situation
preclude any use of force?”
However, we must also look at the
principle of proportionality in terms of self-defense. The question of killing in self-defense was
an important one in early Just War thinking and was generally only justified in
the case of the common good.[6] Why?
Presumably because if it were for the common good, then whatever good
that would come from the actions would outweigh whatever harm was inflicted,
whereas if it were individual self-defense, that might not be the case. However, one could only use means, even for
the common good, that would not tip this balance by causing harm and suffering
beyond what is necessary to achieve the end in question. If unconventional belligerents are more
vulnerable than traditional “combatants,” one is not only making a category
mistake or violating an intuition about justice to treat them the same, but
also violating the principle of proportionality. One could be using more force than is
necessary, more force than can be morally justified, in responding to them. If neutral non-combatants are less vulnerable
than traditional “non-combatants,” treating them in the same manner as the
traditional “non-combatants” also could violate proportionality since more
force could be required, and therefore justified, to defend oneself.
In addition to the moral
considerations in favor of a multi-part distinction, there are also important
practical arguments for expanding the traditional combatant/non-combatant
distinction. First, actual field
practice in recent conflicts would suggest that multiple distinctions within
the traditional distinctions are already in effect. Looking at the examples of Somalia and
Bosnia, these kinds of fine-grained distinctions already seem to be made on the
ground. If in the face of these practices and complexities in war, we insist on
keeping the part distinction, and only those two parts, soldiers may abandon
the distinction altogether since it does not reflect the realities of war or at
least their experiences of war in the field.
Second, despite the fact that combat
and police work do have important differences, there is one similarity: in
contemporary contexts both groups have to deal with using force in situations
where non-combatants are present in areas where there are combatants (or
dangerous individuals). In any given
encounter, police officers are often working in situations where there are
"non-combatants" whom they have a duty to protect, other
"combatants" in the traditional sense (other uniformed officers) and
suspects who might or might not be threatening.
They have to be able to assess the level of threat and to be able to use
the proper force required. Is deadly
force warranted? Could non-lethal
weaponry do the job? If they use more
force than necessary they might kill or harm unjustifiably, while if they use
less force than required they could endanger the "non-combatants" by
not stopping and/or apprehending the suspect. Such a scale of threat assessment
is not considered impractical, unteachable and irrelevant for police work. It
stands to reason that it could be made workable for the military – although
clearly such an approach could not be adopted wholesale, but would have to be
adapted to the various needs of combat, humanitarian and/or peacekeeping
missions.
II.
Before working out the details of a five
part distinction for military operations – whether combat, peacekeeping or
humanitarian intervention missions – it will be helpful to look at some other
models and explore their strengths and weaknesses, and also to consider both
analogies and disanalogies to military operations. The most obvious source of such a model would
be in police work – the so called “Use of Force” models which are often based
upon a continuum-type framework. The idea behind these models is that as the
suspects behavior escalates, then the means that the officer can use to contain
and/or arrest the suspect can also escalate – even to the point of using lethal
force. According to John C. Desmedt, who
formulated one of the first models used in the 1980’s, “The purpose of a use of
force model is to accurately guide a reasonable response for virtually any
situation. Overreaction may not only be
unconstitutional, it may also be ineffective.
Under reaction may allow harm to come to the officer or others.”[7] Such models are used in training, testing and
operational analysis, as well as for litigation to ensure that the department
policy of a given police unit is consistent with the law, as well as its own
training objectives, administrative actions and policies.
In most of the models, there will be
an axis on one end which will, in descending order, delineate various levels of
subject behavior usually including some of the following categories: the
Cooperative Subject, the Resister/Uncooperative Suspect, the Assailant. Within
each of these categories there are often two sub-categories (sometimes called
passive and active) which distinguish different features of that category which
may require different force. First, the
passive, but cooperative suspect is one who is compliant, but initiates her own
compliance without verbal cues from the officer; the active cooperative subject
is compliant with the officer when given verbal cues and instructions. Second, the passive Resister or Uncooperative
Suspect is unresponsive to verbal compliance, is passive in response to cues
from the officer; while the active Uncooperative Suspect is unresponsive and
non-compliant and initiates active steps to avoid any attempts at control by
the office. Third, the passive Assailant
(or more accurately a low level assailant) is aggressively offensive but is not
yet placing the officer in danger of serious bodily injury or death, while the
active assailant does just that.[8]
On the other axis of the model there
will be varying levels of force that the officer can use to control the
situation (remembering that the purpose of the use of force model is control of
the situation and the participants.)[9] In Desmedt’s model one has the following
hierarchy of control mechanisms (in escalating order): social control, verbal
control, weaponless control techniques, electrical shocking devices, chemical
agents, control instruments, impact weapons, firearms (or other weapons that
can result in death or serious injury.)[10] Another use of force model starts with
command presence, moving to verbalization skills, control techniques and
eventually to defensive techniques and/or tools.[11] The Montgomery County, Maryland police
department also uses a four level continuum: “1) Communication/Voice Command,
2) Physical Force, 3) Protective Instruments, 4) Deadly Force.”[12]
How do these two parts of the models
interact? From the standpoint of U.S.
Constitutional law, it is the standard of a reasonable amount of force, not the
minimum amount of force, that is what will determine whether the force used by
a police officer is excessive or not.[13] So the idea in these models is that one would
look at the behavior of the subject or assailant to determine what amount of
force would be reasonable to control that level of behavior. If we imagine these two axes with a diagonal
line running between them, on one side of the diagonal lies an areas of
probable ineffective control and on the other side lies probable excessive
force. In between these two areas is
where reasonable force lies, the area where the officer can have effective
control of the situation (to also avoid harm to the officer and other civilians
in the vicinity) without using excessive (and unlawful) force.
For our purposes, what is valuable in
these models is that fact that subjects are categorized into multiple
categories and that the level of force to be used is indexed to their behaviors
that the officer can observe in the situation.
However, this does not mean that these models are uncontroversial or
without concerns, especially with regard to their implementation. First, it has been objected that these models
are too mechanical and automatic to meet the legal standard of reasonableness.[14] In legal cases one wants to know what the
reasonable police officer would have thought in that situation, how the
reasonable police officer would have perceived the threat posed by the behavior
of the suspect and the force necessary to control that situation. This suggests that these kinds of assessments
are the product of training, intelligence and professional experience which
cannot be gained from a simple chart; they must be able to use these skills and
experiences in the assessments, for which these models can be a guide, not the
beginning and end of the model.
Second, some commentators have raised
the serious concern of hesitation in field situations.[15]
The argument is that since many of these continuum models are progressively
sequentially in nature, the officer has to go through the process of the
various steps of the model in deciding what force to use and this puts
hesitation into the situation. This hesitation can be deadly, either because it
can allow the situation to escalate more quickly as the subject sees there is
hesitation or because the officer may hesitate too long in eliminating the less
intrusive force option, when in fact stronger force is called for to quickly
control and deescalate the situation.
This concern centers around the time that is necessary for even the
well-trained officer to go through the continuum and make her assessment about
the behavior exhibited and the appropriate level of force; clearly in volatile,
fluid and unpredictable law enforcement situations, time is one of the most
precious commodities. Instead, the
argument goes, the focus should be on training officer to learn the skills of
subjective threat assessment and to accurately be able to know when deadly or
serious force is necessary and apply it effectively.
What would a threat assessment model
look like? First, it is important to define precisely what one means by threat:
“A threat is a capability to do harm joined by hostile intent.”[16] Therefore, threat assessment training should
emphasize indicators of capability to do harm, as well as indicators of hostile
intent, since the goal such training is to allow officers to recognize an
immanent threat and to respond in a timely matter. Indicators of intent can be difficult to
isolate, but might include verbal and non-verbal communication, along with
noncompliance with clear verbal commands of an officer. Indicators of capability are more tangible
and can include: possession or access to a weapon (even the officer’s),
demonstrated combat skill or ability, size or fitness of the suspect or the
presence of multiple subjects. Looking
at the FBI’s training methods, one can see the following four examples of a
deadly threat: 1) possession of or an attempting to gain possession of a
weapon; 2) armed suspect running to gain cover; 3) subject who demonstrates
intention or capability to inflict serious injury or death without a weapon; 4)
subject is trying to escape vicinity of violent confrontation in which he
inflicted or attempted to inflict injury or death.[17]
The idea with a threat assessment
model, as opposed to the use of force model, is that if a clear and serious
threat exists then the officer can immediately respond with adequate force,
without the delay that it is argued the use of force model brings. If threat assessment suggests that it is not
a deadly or violent threat, then the officer can take the necessary time to
consider a range of non-deadly options.
However, it should be noted that other options are only to be considered
if the officer assesses the threat to be non-deadly or non-violent; otherwise
this model suggests that the officer should respond immediately with strong
force. The difference between the two
models is that the use of force model, it is argued, tends to wait and see how
the threat manifests itself and then to respond more stronger as the threat escalates;
the threat assessment model wants to look to see if strong, especially deadly
force, is appropriate and if it is, then implement it quickly and if it is not,
then take time to consider the appropriate level of force. In short, the idea is for the officer to
associate the use of force with the presence of a threat; when the threat
ceases or decreases, then the type and amount of force can be modified
accordingly.[18]
With these two models in mind, how
applicable might either or both of these law enforcement models be to how
soldiers use legitimate force (against combatants, not against non-combatants)
in warfare? What are the analogies to
warfare? To answer this question, it
might be helpful to have a working definition of police work, as a point of
comparison. One source defines policing
as follows: “They are representatives of the state whose responsibility is to
intervene proactively and reactively to a wide range of disturbances…police are
professional interveners.”[19] Further, police must do the following four
things in any encounter: 1) they must seek information about the situation; 2)
they must attend to the overt behavior of the civilians in their presence; 3)
they must be treated by civilians in a respectful manner, otherwise their
status is threatened; 4) they must achieve an appropriate resolution or outcome
to the situation.[20]
Given this understanding of police
work, one could argue that both police and soldiers use lethal force in their
encounters and must further, need to know when to use this force, on whom it
can be legitimately used and when it cannot be legitimately used (particularly
against uninvolved civilians.) Further,
in both police work and combat one is responsible and accountable for both the
force that one uses and for the protection of uninvolved civilians/non-combatants. In both areas the use of excessive force is
viewed as morally and legally illegitimate and can be a crime for which the
individual can be held responsible. Such
excessive force is viewed as endangering the community that is represented, but
also as a betrayal of the code to which police and soldiers claim
obedience. On the other hand,
insufficient use of force can endanger other colleagues (other officers or
soldiers) as well as the civilians that one is sworn to protect. Both groups are involved (especially in
contemporary warfare which can involve standard combat, peacekeeping,
humanitarian missions – or more often a combination of all of these) in fluid
and potentially volatile situations where the combatants and non-combatants
(officers, suspects and civilians) are in the same physical proximity. Consequently, individuals need to make quick,
but accurate assessments based in information/intelligence in the field,
usually without much time for deliberation or reflection. Finally, it could be argued that in both
situations training and teamwork with ones colleagues are essential for a good,
timely and ethical response. Without
these elements, the situation could get further out of hand and result in unnecessary
injury or death.
Despite the considerable analogies
between military operations and police work, there is a considerable and
important objection that there are also a number of disanalogies between the
two, that they are very different kinds of things. While police officers can and do interact
using lethal force, very few (proportionally speaking) of their encounters
involve the use of lethal or potentially lethal force; most of their
interactions involve verbal and non-verbal communication as a major tool of
control and achieving their desired outcome.
However, with military operations (notably combat) this is not possible
and in fact, many more encounters will involve the use of lethal or potentially
lethal force. (One can argue that this
analogy holds better with peacekeeping and humanitarian interventions which
seem to involve more police-type encounters, but there is the still the
consideration that lethal and potentially force is employed to a greater degree
than in domestic police work.) In the
military, lethal and potentially lethal force is the form; in police work it is
the largely the exception.
Another disanalogy comes from the
emphasis one could argue that the military places on teamwork, espirit de corps, in training, in codes
of honor and professionalism and in actual operations. In police work, especially domestic police
work, it is the individual officer (although backed up by others as necessary)
that is the basic organizational unit; in the military, it is rarely the
individual soldier acting alone that is the basic organizational unit, but a
small group of individuals working together.
Therefore in military operations, teamwork and the chain of command is
much more important than the individual decision-making ability of one person. (Once again, one could modify this argument a
bit to suggest that the group responsible in humanitarian and peacekeeping
operations is much smaller and may, in fact, be an individual soldier – or a
couple – and is more analogous to police work.) A reason for this difference is that the
essential functions of these two groups are quite different: the police are
charged with maintaining civil order and protecting the public and property;
soldiers (at least in combat situations) at charged with defeating the enemy,
getting the other combatants to surrender or cease fighting, and protecting or
at least abstaining from inflicting harm on non-combatants.
So if there seem to be some analogies
between military operations and police work and yet there are some important
differences, where does leave us? In
particular, how helpful will ‘use of force’ or ‘threat assessment’ models taken
from police work be in working out a multi-part combatant/non-combatant
distinction? First, I think that we can
conclude that in peacekeeping, humanitarian interventions and other non-conventional combat situations there are
more analogies to police work and therefore, the ‘use of force’ models could be
helpful. However, because of the disanalogies
(especially in conventional combat situations) any model should have a heavy
threat assessment component. Any ‘use of
force’ model we employ for military operations (regardless of the kind) should
be approached in descending order – starting with the highest level of force
applicable and reducing the force as the threat reduces or is controlled. Most ‘use of force’ models in police work
assume an ascending model of force where one starts with the least amount of
force and call for increasing it as the situation or suspect behaviors
escalate; this approach will clearly be problematic in military operations
where the use of lethal force is much more likely and it is less likely that
one can use verbal or other non-lethal options to deal with the situation.
What I will argue in the next section
is that a soldier use a threat assessment kind of approach to determine whether
the individual belongs in the combatant on non-combatant category, and then
within that category, she can employ something more like a use of force model
(in descending order of threat) to ascertain what level of force is justified
depending on where they fall within the combatant category (is the subject an
unconventional belligerent or merely hostile?) or the non-combatant category
(is the person neutral or vulnerable?)
This allows us to make use of the insights that might be gained from
domestic police models, while at the same time recognizing the important
differences between police work and military operations.
III.
What exactly would this multi-part
distinction look like? How might it work
in the field? To begin with, this scale is designed to have the ability to be
somewhat flexible in its application.
Clearly there are areas of ambiguity that the traditional
combatant/non-combatant distinction cannot accommodate, but it is important not
to give up assignations of responsibility, nor to deny the moral difference
between those who threaten and cause harm and those who do not. Rather, I want to suggest a pragmatic way in
which this distinction can be understood and applied in the complex and fluid
situations that are characteristic of contemporary war. This scale could
especially help those in the field to make a determination of the potential
threat that is involved in a given situation, and therefore give guidance on
how best to act consistent with
International Law and the ‘rules’ of war.
The
idea behind this scale is to incorporate the necessity of threat assessment
with the flexibility of the use of force models that we discussed above. The first determination that would need to be
made is whether the person in question is a combatant or non-combatant (or is
likely to be one or the other since it certainly can be unclear). Once this determination is made then the
question of how to treat this person, precisely how much force is to be used
and how can be made by looking at what kind of combatant they might be or what
kind of non-combatant they might be.
This is where, even in dealing with a combatant, one might modify the
kind and extent of force that one is using depending on the circumstance –
whether the situation is a tradition combat situation, a peacekeeping or
humanitarian mission. To begin, let us
look at each step in the model from the standpoint of threat assessment: What
are the intentions of the subject? What
are capabilities of that person to carry out any intentions?
The first and highest level of threat
on this scale would be that of the uniformed combat personnel. This would be an individual with a
standardized (at least to his own military context) uniform with discernable
symbols and identification which announce him as such to those who might see
him. This person carries a weapon
openly, often travels in structured groups of his colleagues; it can be
ascertained from a distance that his intentions are likely to be hostile, that
he has the ability to carry out these intentions and therefore, poses the
highest level of threat to a possible enemy.
This category is how the combatant in conventional warfare has usually
been defined and in a conventional combat situation, it is expected that this
is the kind of combatant to be encountered.
Since this type of individual clearly poses the largest threat on the
scale, the level of responsibility he must meet should also be high.
The second level of threat would be an
armed individual (or unconventional belligerent), but not necessarily or obviously in a standard uniform that clearly
announces her intentions. Since this
person is armed, it is likely (though not certain) that her intentions are
hostile and since her intentions are not evident, but a weapon is, this
comprises a fairly serious threat. It
may turn out that she has no hostile intention at all, but the presence of a
weapon at least raises concern and potential threat, thus placing her
potentially in the combatant category.
The fact that the intentions are not announced also points to the
potential threat and therefore, she should be viewed as a threat and having a
great deal of power – at least until such time as she announces her intentions
(which would either move her up or down the scale definitively.) One might encounter this kind of combatant in
a conventional combat situation, raising questions about whether she is also to
be treated with the same force that one would use against a conventional
combatant, but more likely this is the highest level of combatant that one
would see in peacekeeping and humanitarian type missions.
The third level of threat would be
classified as hostile. In this level the
intentions of the individuals are not made clear by a uniform or other symbol
which announces their intentions and it is also not clear whether or not they
have weapons (or have easy access to them).
However, these individuals may meet a certain description that fits
potentially hostile forces, be present in an area where such individuals are
suspected of operating or in some other way persuade the on-looker that they
are neither neutral nor vulnerable (levels four and five of the non-combatant
end of the scale.) While this is admittedly
somewhat ambiguous, it is necessary to leave this category somewhat open in
order to accommodate differences between combat missions and those that are
humanitarian or peacekeeping in nature.
(In the later two situations one may able to gather intelligence or use
verbal skills to question the person or their compatriots, whereas in a combat
situation one may have to assume they are hostile until non-verbal cues or
behavior indicates otherwise.) Clearly,
what looks ‘hostile’ in a combat situation may differ from other situations, or
vice versa. Another important component
in this level is the fluidity of the situation, such that events and situations
are highly volatile and subject to change, which makes the ambiguity of
intentions and weapon possession dangerous.
At this point, it is essential to
stress that that these first three categories are all different variations on
the traditional combatant category; these individuals are all to be treated (in
relative degree) more or less as one would treat a combatant. This also means that there is a clear
conceptual distinction between levels three and four/five (even though
individuals may might move from the combatant categories to the non-combatant
categories.) Levels four and five are
non-combatants and are entitled to the protections associated with those groups
(neutral powers and “innocents”) under International Law and the rules/customs
of war.
The fourth level of threat would be
classified as one who is neutral or non-hostile. In this case the individual appears to
announce no hostile intentions (symbolically by dress or insignia, by the
presence of a weapon, or by verbal or non-verbal communication) but neither has
she announced friendly intentions nor is evincing open cooperation with
military forces. In terms of capability,
she may have indicated (or opposing soldiers may have discerned) that she has
no weapon, no easy access nor made an attempt to gain one. As long as she maintains her
neutrality/non-hostility, she could be considered to be a fairly minimal
threat, but clearly if the neutrality appears to change then her status would
move to either the third or final category.
If the neutral stance is maintained then this person is not a threat,
and responsibility should be rendered accordingly.
The final level of threat would be one
who is classified as vulnerable. Any
hostile intentions that may be exhibited (i.e. a prisoner in uniform, angry
speech) are counter-acted by a clear inability or lack of desire to act on
them. This individual poses a very
minimal (minimal – not zero – because they might change their status and this
has to be accounted for) threat and, in fact, may require positive protection
from other hostile forces. Clearly many
of the people who are traditionally classified as non-combatants would fall
into this category (most children, women, the old, prisoners and the infirm or
injured) and should be accorded the usual protections that we think of because
they clearly pose little threat and may be threatened themselves – with no
recourse to defend themselves.
So how might one implement this
scale in the field? First, let us look
at a conventional combat situation (i.e. ground war in Iraq.) In such a situation is it likely that one will
encounter persons in the first and possibly the second levels as well as
possibly the fourth and fifth categories.
Clearly one must immediately ascertain whether one has a combatant or
non-combatant. If the person turns out
the be a non-combatant, then one can immediately lower the force used to be
adequate to deal with level four (controlling the situation) while one
ascertains what kind of non-combatant is involved. If one decides that this person is in fact
level five (the traditional non-combatant in need of protection) then one can
further modify ones tactics.
On the other hand, if one ascertains
that the person is a combatant (either it being clear that they are or one has
a suspicion of hostility) then the soldier should start with force in
accordance with level one or two. If the
person is a conventional belligerent and obviously so, one would start with
that scale of force and if not, one starts with level two force and moves down
the scale if it becomes clear that less force is necessary. It would be well to point out that in many combat
situations (both conventional and asymmetrical) level three persons could
actually be more dangerous simply in virtue of what is not known, so that the
force differential between levels two and three may be minimal if there is any
difference at all. In all three of these
levels, the person is a combatant (or is considered as a combatant) and so
lethal force could be legitimate.
Second, let us look at how this
scale might work in the case of a peacekeeping operation (e.g. Bosnia) where
U.S. forces are charged with keeping opposing forces in check and/or keeping
civil order. In such a situation, one
may encounter level one personnel as combatants, but it is much more likely
that one will be dealing with levels two and three, as well as level four and five
non-combatants. In any case, one will
still need to be able to discern combatants from non-combatants as in the above
combat scenario. If it is determined
that one is dealing with combatants, then one would start with the highest
level of force applicable (likely to be level two) and modify in descending
order if that becomes appropriate. For
example, it may turn out one has simply hostile forces who could turn out to be
non-hostile non-combatants (in the event you determine they are not armed), but
for now it is clear that they are hostile and not clear whether or not they are
armed. In this situation, you might use
less force than you would in a similar combat situation (because the
individuals in question could be non-combatants and also it is likely that
there are non-combatants in the area), but because of the potential danger
(level three is still a combatant category) one may still need to keep ready
lethal force.
Third, in a humanitarian
intervention (e.g. Somalia where the US military is charged with delivering
food) it is likely that you have even more non-combatants in the areas and
probably are dealing with level three combatants (although level two combatants
could also show up to disrupt the situation).
In this case one probably has to assume level three combatants with a
force appropriate to dealing with level of threat, but also not unduly
endangering the surrounding non-combatants.
To further complicate matters, it may turn out that the level three
combatants are level two combatants in disguise and so the soldier has to be
prepared for that possibility, but keep that level of force in check until the
presence of weapons is ascertained. In
peacekeeping and humanitarian missions, the force differential between levels
two and three could be significant (lethal force vs. other methods of control
more like conventional police work) and so the difference between these two
levels becomes more important to establish.
In these two kinds of operations, individuals could easy move from level
three to level four (you ascertain they do not have a weapon) or vice versa
(they begin exhibiting hostile behaviors or gain access to a weapon as a
situation escalates) and so one has to modify the kind of force that is
appropriate in level three accordingly.
To sum up, whatever situation the
military operation finds itself in, the first matter of business is to
ascertain whether the individual is a combatant or non-combatant since that
will determine which end of the scale one begins with in determining the level
of force. If the person is a
non-combatant, then we start with a much lower level of force, if any at all;
if the person is a combatant, then one starts with the highest level of force
appropriate to the likely kind of combatants – modifying (usually reducing) the
level force necessary as finer determinations are made about the kind of
combatant involved and the threat posed.
Clearly the difference in how one treats a hostile combatant versus a
non-conventional belligerent in a combat situation may not be that drastic, but
I believe those differences will be much more significant in peacekeeping and
humanitarian missions. What I want to
suggest is that we can still maintain the traditional distinction with its
attendant moral considerations, but also recognize that there are various
levels of gray (especially in how one might present as a combatant) that may
call for different levels of force and may require some fluidity in how one
applies that force. I think that a five
part model such as I have outlined above can do just that.
IV.
Naturally there are numerous
concerns and objections that would be raised to any such model, but I want to
concentrate on three. First, one might
object that this model relies too heavily on the law enforcement model and is,
consequently at odds with how the military operates since the police and the
military have too very different purposes.
The majority of police work is concerned with maintaining civil order
and apprehending and controlling those who resist or who are a danger to that
civil order; the police do not need to defeat an enemy, but only need to be
able to exert control in the situation long enough to resolve it. On the other hand, military operations are
largely concerned with defeating the enemy and mastering control of a physical
area beyond just restoring civil order, which involves sophisticated
technologies, strategies and extensive teamwork to bring this about. It could
also be argued that there are serious differences in organizational structure,
training methods and institutional values which also require very different
approaches. In short, we are comparing
apples and oranges.
While it is true that this model does rely heavily
on a multi-part distinction which has analogies to the use of force models
found in domestic police work, I would argue that the five part model I have
suggested is based upon military considerations – both moral and
practical. In the last half of the 20th
century militaries (especially in the developing world) were engaged in
military operations where it seemed increasingly difficult to distinguish the
combatants from the non-combatants; in engagements like Vietnam one could argue
that the distinction had been abandoned
de facto as the realities of the battlefield seemed to eclipse morality and
military (not to mention legal) conventions.
What I have tried to do is to use a five part distinction to argue that
it is possible to maintain this important distinction (with its necessary moral
and legal protections for non-combatants), but only if we expand the
distinction to recognize that there are different kinds of non-combatants, and
especially that there are different kinds of combatants. Using a “one kind of force fits all” model
ultimately undermines the very distinction that it seeks to preserve,
especially when battlefield requirements and realities seem to fly in the face
of the distinction.
Second, one could reasonably object
(especially if one is charged with the teaching and training of young military
personnel) that such a model is too complicated to teach and learn in the
classroom, much less implement in the field.
It is in answer to this objection that I think the analogies to law
enforcement are useful, especially in the cases of peacekeeping and humanitarian
missions. While the use of force models
are not uncomplicated and not without their critics, the fact that they have
been used in police departments and law enforcement agencies for nearly twenty
years, have been taught in the course of standard training and have also legal,
especially constitutional, scrutiny by lawyers and the courts suggests that it
is neither impractical, nor impossible.
That, however, is not to suggest that it is easy either. I recognize that my model does add an
additional layer of discussion to the teaching of the combatant/non-combatant
distinction that takes place in the academies, OTC, ROTC, basic training and in
the field. Rather than just focusing on
the differences between combatants and non-combatants, I am also asking
students and teacher to reflect on what a combatant in its various
incarnations, and a non-combatant in its various incarnations, might look like
and what level of force is legitimate in dealing with them.
However, I would also argue that many of these conversations
are already happening as students,
teachers and military professionals alike grapple with the difficulty of
applying and maintaining this distinction in complex, contemporary
warfare. What this model does it to give
a voice to those conversations, and a way to sort out that confusion both in
the classroom and on the battlefield in a way that I believe is consistent with
the moral considerations that drive the distinction (and the larger apparatus
of Just War theory) and the military traditions and considerations that up it.
Third, the most serious objection is
that such a model undermines the original intentions (especially the moral
ones) of the traditional combatant/non-combatant distinction and would further
erode the distinction, rather than shore it up – as I have argued. The main area of concern would likely be the
third and forth levels where there is some necessary gray area. In level three, if it is not clear whether or
not the individual has a weapon, why should they be considered a
combatant? Would not be better to
consider them a non-combatant until one can make that determination? On the other hand, persons who get assigned
as level four non-combatants could very well combatants in disguise or be
potentially dangerous, does the fact that someone does not have a weapon make
them not a threat? Rather than clearing
up the gray area that is so problematic in maintaining the distinction, this
model actually seems to add to the problem by further institutionalizing this
ambiguity.
The intention behind the distinction is to protect
the non-combatants from being unjustifiably harmed and to ensure that force is
used only against those whom it is justified, namely the combatants. Any model
which asks soldiers to take seriously the question of how much and what kind of
force they need to use against the enemy and helps them better identify those
against who they should use this force, as opposed to those against whom it
should not be used, will further this end.
Rather than undermining the intentions of the distinction, I believe
that such a model could potentially reduce the unfortunately incidents of
“collateral damage” as soldiers have more options about how, when and to what
extent they use force. The original
distinction asks us to take serious that there are moral and practical
differences between combatants and non-combatants which at the core of fighting
a war justly; this model simply tries to more clearly articulate what each of
these categories might look like – taking into account the complexities and
ambiguities of contemporary combat, peacekeeping and humanitarian operations.
Conclusion
In this paper I have outlined and defended in more
detail a five-part combatant and non-combatant distinction which is intended to
do two things: first, this model tries to account for the considerable
difficulty in sorting out the different varieties of combatant and the
different varieties on non-combatants that one might encounter in military
operations; second, rather than arguing for a sliding scale, this model simply
expands the two traditional categories and thus maintains in tact the crucial
moral insight that there is a difference between those who can be legitimately
targeted and those against whom such targeting is a war crime. The ‘threat assessment’ and ‘use of force’
models from domestic police work do provide some useful practical insights in
how this model might work, but it was also necessary to make some serious
alterations to account for the differences between military operations (combat,
peacekeeping or humanitarian) and domestic police work. Therefore, soldiers would first need to use a
threat assessment model to ascertain whether the person in question is a
combatant or a non-combatant (or is likely to be) and then determine within
that category what kind of force or tactics are justified (i.e. neither
endangering non-combatants or fellow soldiers, nor using more force than
necessary) to achieve the end in question.
The hope is that a distinction which maintains the moral difference, but
also has some flexibility as to how force is to be applied – especially in
different kinds of military situations – will encourage soldiers to continue to
maintain and implement the distinction, despite the complexities and
ambiguities of the contemporary battlefield.
NOTES
[1] For a more complete version of this argument, see
“Innocence Lost” JSCOPE 2002
[2] Michael Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars
(New York: Basic Books, 1991), p. 145.
[3] A corollary can be drawn to the criminal justice system with its extensive taxonomy designed to classify and assess the danger to the community of various kinds of lawbreakers in a way that answers the above questions. A criminal who has been charged with first degree murder is taken much more seriously, as much more of a threat, than one who has been charged with involuntary manslaughter or fraud. These distinctions are important in fairly determining how bail will be set before the trial process and in the nature of punishment that will be sought in the sentencing phase. However, not all first degree murderers are treated the same, especially in the sentencing phase when the jury and/or judge may consider various circumstances which could increase or mitigate the punishment. They might look at the circumstances of the crime, a prior record, evidence of remorse and possible danger to the community, which can all affect the length and type of sentence; some of these factors will also have been used in the determination of responsibility in the conviction phase.
[4] Ibid., p. 146.
[5] The principle of proportionality can be understood as follows: the good or end to be achieved by the war must outweigh the harm inflicted to achieve that end, with the implication that one ought to only use enough force to achieve the end and no more. The principle of proportionality can be understood as follows: the good or end to be achieved by the war must outweigh the harm inflicted to achieve that end, with the implication that one ought to only use enough force to achieve the end and no more.
[6] See Thomas Aquinas, On Law, Morality and
Politics ed. William P. Baumgarth
and Richard J. Regan S.J. (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1988), p. 226-7.
[7] John C. Desmedt, “The (Original) Use of Force
Model: The Physical Intervention Paradigm for Enforcement and
Corrections,” 1995 www.protectivesafetysystems.com/uofm.htm
[8] Ibid., p.9ff.
See also www.cleet.state.ok.us/pdf (January 20, 2003) for a slightly different
model.
[9] Ibid., p. 21.
[10] Ibid.
[11] www.cleet.state.ok.us/pdf (January 20, 2003)
[12] Edward R. Hickey and Joel Garner, The Rate of
Force Used by the Police in Montgomery County, Maryland: A Report to the
Montgomery County Department of the Police and the National Institute of
Justice. March 2002, p. 1-5.
[13] Thomas D. Petrowski, “ Use of force policies and
training: a reasoned approach,” (Part I)
The FBI Law Enforcement Bulletin
October 2002, p. 1-2.
[14] Ibid.
[15] Ibid., p. 4.
[16] Thomas D. Petrowski, “ Use of force policies and
training: a reasoned approach,” (Part
II) The FBI Law Enforcement Bulletin
November 2002, p. 1-2.
[17] Ibid. p. 2.
[18] Ibid., p. 5.
[19] Richard E. Sykes and Edward E. Brent, Policing:
A Social Behaviorist Perspective. (New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University
Press, 1983), p. 26.
[20] Ibid., p. 60-1.