The Ethics of Assassination
Whit Kaufman
The
In this essay I will analyze the
ethics of political assassination from with the context of the Just War
tradition, with the aim of moving toward developing a framework within which
the question of assassination can be addressed.
Just War doctrine involves a strong presumption against the use of
violence or killing (in peacetime or in war) outside of certain limited
contexts, specifically the punishment of the guilty, self-defense against an
unjust attacker, and the enforcement of natural justice or law. Even in those contexts, the use of violence
is subject to the requirements of necessity, proportionality, noncombatant
immunity, and right motive. Neither the
desire for revenge, nor the motive of maximizing good consequences, can serve
as a legitimate basis for the use of violence in Just War Doctrine. What then is the moral status of political
assassination in Just War theory?
A first issue is of course the
problem of defining ‘assassination’, a term which is very difficult to pin
down. Let us begin by dismissing the
idea that assassination essentially involves treachery, betrayal, or
perfidy. Caspar Weinberger has argued
that when assassination is forbidden in the law of armed conflict, what is
meant is “murder by treacherous means,”[2] and that therefore
there is nothing wrong with assassination per se, so long as it does not
involve “treachery.” This argument
however is a red herring. While there
may be an additional moral constraint against the use of treachery
(perhaps derived from the chivalric tradition, as Thomas Wingfield suggests),
it is clear that the central moral concern about assassination is not the
presence of a betrayal of trust, but rather the morality of premeditated,
extrajudicial killing of specific individuals, typically those in leadership
positions (by treachery or not). Such
actions would ordinarily be considered simply murder, and the question is
whether there is sufficient moral basis for permitting such a prima facie
wrongful act. Some commentators have
adopted the term “targeted killing” so as to avoid any connotations of
treachery associated with the term “assassination.”[3] However, in this essay I will use the term
“assassination” to mean targeted killing, without reference to
“treachery.” The moral question is then
whether targeted killings are permissible or not under Just War Doctrine.
A second issue we will have to
examine is whether there is an essential difference between military and
political leaders as regards the legitimacy of assassination. It is often assumed that military leaders, as
they are obviously combatants under Just War principles, are legitimate targets
in wartime, and therefore it is permissible to assassinate them (so long as no
treachery is used). Political leaders
such as Saddam Hussein or Fidel Castro, some have argued, are different: they
are not obviously combatants, even where he has ultimate control over the
military. Similar difficult questions
concern countries where the commander of the military is a civilian, as in the
The question to be faced then is
the following: is there a moral basis for a policy of premeditated,
extrajudicial killing, and does it depend on whether the target is a military
or merely political leader? Discussion
of this question is often muddled by a failure to clearly distinguish the
punishment rationale from the self-defense rationale for assassination. Indeed, the idea of justifying a policy of
assassination under the rubric of punishment would seem to run into intractable
moral problems, for a policy of summary execution without trial or any
significant procedural constraints would not ordinarily be considered a
legitimate form of punishment.
Weinberger’s confusion on this issue is exemplary: he begins with a Just
War defensive rationale for targeting leaders on the grounds that they are
combatants (22), then switches to a punishment argument (“there is every reason
to punish the leaders for the acts that brought on the war”), and ends with a
consequentialist rationale for assassination (“killing leaders may end a war
with a big saving of soldiers’ lives” (id.)).
He concludes that if killing the leaders would not violate the laws of
armed conflict, “then clearly the taking of any enemy commander (without any
treachery) and holding him for trial conducted under normal national rules
would not violate any moral or legal prohibition” (24). But the confusions in this argument are
legion. The Just War tradition, as I
have said, does not obviously dictate that heads of state are combatants[4], and in any case
Weinberger’s invocation of consequentialist justifications are clearly ruled
out under Just War Doctrine. More
importantly, the syllogism with which Weinberger concludes his essay -- that if
killing the leader is permissible, then trying him is permissible -- is not
legitimate. What is clear is that
capturing an enemy commander and placing him on trial is morally and legally
permissible. What is not clear is
whether intentionally killing him -- without benefit of trial -- is
permissible.
Given that the punishment
rationale for extrajudicial assassination seems so obviously inapt, and given
that most commentators do not want to resort to the Realist/consequentialist
reasoning that Weinberger invokes, it is no surprise that most defenders of the
assassination policy invoke a self-defense rationale. Thus for example Defense Secretary Donald
Rumsfeld reportedly told CNN that “the
Beres asserts that in certain
circumstances, the resort to assassination would be “decidedly rational and
humane” (id.). It is important to
acknowledge just how tempting the idea of assassination is even from a moral
standpoint. It offers a trade of a
single death to avoid the death of millions, and as former White House press
secretary Ari Fleischer put it, "The cost of one bullet, if the Iraqi
people take it on themselves, is substantially less" than going to
war. Perhaps more pertinently, it
appears to vindicate our moral sense, in that assassination goes directly after
the responsible, indeed morally guilty parties, rather than after the
“innocent” soldiers who in most cases are merely following orders, often under
duress (as for instance in the Iraqi army).
Thus both utilitarian and moral rationales appear to support the
practice of assassination.
But this temptation is deceptive. If the justification for killing in war is
defensive, then neither of the above factors is morally relevant. The doctrine of self-defense, as we have
said, is distinct from the consequentialist or Realist rationale which aims to
minimize overall costs, or simply adopt the most effective strategy. But equally important, moral guilt or
innocence is not directly relevant to the use of defensive force; force is
justified against a guilty or an innocent aggressor. What justifies the force is the unjust
aggression, not the innocence or guilt of the aggressor. Thus it is crucial to understand the nature
of the justification for killing, and avoid conflating incompatible moral
theories.
But suppose we try to address
the self-defense issue, shed of the misleading connections to deterrence,
punishment, and consequentialism. The
question of the ethics of political assassination can be stated more
clearly. Do the principles of defensive
force justify a policy of targeted assassination of military or political
leaders? More broadly, can a
premeditated killing ever satisfy the moral principles of self-defense? Here I understand the moral right of
self-defense as a right to use necessary and proportionate force against an
imminent unjust attack, with the motive of protecting oneself or others from
serious harm. The force must be
necessary, in that there are no nonviolent or less harmful alternative means of
preventing the attack; it must be also proportionate in the sense that the harm
being used is proportionate to the harm being prevented.
The
harm must also be imminent, i.e. immediate, about to happen. Thus Daniel Webster’s famous definition of
imminence: the “necessity of that self-defense is instant, overwhelming, and
leaving no choice of means, and no moment for deliberation.”[8] Finally, I will assume for simplicity’s sake
in this essay that the target of the attack is uncontroversially an unjust
aggressor (e.g. Hussein, bin Laden, Hamas leaders); where the target is neither
unjust nor an aggressor the attack will obviously be impermissible in itself.
It is often taken as
uncontroversial and unproblematic that military leaders are legitimate military
targets, given their presence in the chain of command -- and sometimes this is
extended to political leaders too, so long as they direct the military. Thomas Wingfield for instance approvingly
cites Schmitt: “lawful targeting in wartime has never required that the
individual actually be engaged in combat.
Rather, it depends on combatant status.
The general directing operations miles from battle is as valid a target
as the commander leading his troops in combat. The same applies to Saddam
Hussein. Once he became a combatant, the
law of war clearly permitted targeting him.”[9] But, even apart from the logical leap between
military commanders and heads of state, the chief error in this passage is what
we might call the formalist fallacy.
Just War Theory indeed is often accused of formalism (sometimes called
“essentialism”), of making combatancy simply determined by one’s formal role,
as if one can simply read off one’s combatant status by identifying the essence
of one’s role. But this is I think a
mischaracterization and an unfair criticism of Just War Theory.
Stephen Kershnar thus accuses
the Just War Theory of arguing that certain roles have “essences” that in turn
determine one’s status as combatant or noncombatant.[10] A doctor’s essential role is to heal, a
farmer’s essential role is to grow food; hence they are not combatants. But a soldier’s -- and a military leader’s --
essential role is to fight, thus making him a combatant. The question of whether a political leader is
a legitimate target then comes down to the question of whether his role is
essentially one connected to aggression.
Kershnar rightfully criticizes this view as clumsy and
unconvincing. Indeed, it is not even
clear on this view whether the political leader is a combatant or not -- is the
nature of his role political leadership, or military leadership? The formalist doctrine is also unhelpful in
its application to terrorism, where there is no war and thus no combatancy in
the technical sense. But it is also
wrong, I would argue, because it mischaracterizes Just War Theory.
In the Just War Doctrine,
combatancy is not simply determined by one’s formal status, but rather by one’s
current and ongoing actions: i.e. whether they constitute aggression or
not. A soldier who lays down his
weapons, or is no longer a threat, is no longer a combatant for purposes of
exercising one’s right to use deadly force.
He may be captured, but he may not be shot. Correspondingly, a civilian who takes up arms
and attempts aggressive action is a legitimate target, despite not being a
combatant in the formal or essential sense.
In other words, there is no avoiding a substantive analysis of the
notion of combatancy. One is a combatant
to the extent one is presently engaging in unjustified aggression; one is a
noncombatant to the extent one is not a present or imminent threat. The paradigm of the combatant, then, is the
soldier with the weapon pointed at you.
On this view, it is not automatically true that a military leader is a
combatant in the strict sense -- and it even more difficult to say whether a
political leader – who is typically unarmed and not a fighter -- constitutes a
combatant. There is no avoiding a
substantive analysis of these questions (hence Chayes’ point about Hussein, so
brusquely dismissed by Wingfield and Schmitt).
For there are two questions we must ask about the potential target of an
assassination attempt: 1) is he an aggressor?
and 2) does he pose an imminent threat?
To justify assassination, at a minimum these two questions will have to
be answered in the affirmative.
But how can we answer such a
question? What I would suggest is that
we must resort to the substantive criteria for aggression. Jeffrie Murphy’s definition of aggression
provides a good starting point: “What I
mean by this [i.e., aggression] is that the links of the chain (like the links
between motives and actions) are held together logically and not merely
causally, i.e. all held together, in this case, under the notion of who it is
that is engaged in an attempt to destroy you.”[11] The idea here is that the criteria are more
than merely causal (else doctors and farmers would be aggressors), but have to
do with the nature of one’s agency. Is
one a direct agent in the unjustified aggression? Thomas Wingfield concedes that merely being a
“regime elite” does not render one a legitimate target; this only applies to
those members “participating in or taking an active role in directing military
operations” (311). But even this is too
weak. Again, the paradigm case is the
person actually engaging in the use of violence. With those in a supervisory role, the presumption
must be against killing them, unless their role is immediate and direct in the
act of aggression. This is especially
the case where it is they who are actually initiating the acts, i.e. issuing
orders to subordinates to carry out acts of violence – as opposed to merely
being the conduit of orders. (It should be noted that ‘aggression’ refers to
both external and internal violence: attacks on other countries, or unjustified
attacks on one’s own people, as say Hitler’s policy of genocide or Hussein’s
use of chemical weapons on the Kurds.)
Clearly, military leaders will
be far more likely to qualify as part of the direct chain of aggression than
will political leaders. On this
analysis, there can be no simple answer as to whether a given political leader
is an aggressor, and hence a legitimate target in war. The answer will depend on the extent of
involvement with the waging and oversight of the aggression, including
importantly the extent to which he provides the initiative for the war itself,
or for particular acts of aggression within it.
The political structure of the society will obviously be relevant; in a
dictatorship, there is far more centralized control of state functions, and
thus a much stronger presumption of direct responsibility on the part of the
ruler. In a democracy, in contrast, the
leader may be acting as the agent of the legislature or the people in general,
and may be far removed from the vast majority of wartime decisions. Even having the ultimate responsibility for
giving the green light to war does not necessarily constitute the leader as an
aggressor -- it will depend on such factors as whether he is the initiator or
merely a figurehead, providing a rubber stamp.
But it seems that political leaders are sufficiently different than
military leaders such that the ordinary presumption of combatancy must not
apply to the former category.
But even if we were to declare a
given political leader to be an aggressor, would the imminence standard be
satisfied? A political leader is not
ordinarily an imminent threat, neither himself threatening immediate harm nor
directing others to do so. The mere
expectation that killing the leader might end the war does not by itself
constitute a grounds for such an attack; that would be to revert to the
deterrence rationale rather than self-defense.
However, if a political leader were directly involved in the
hostilities, and were say on the verge of ordering a nuclear strike, or
authorizing an act of terrorism, then the imminence standard would probably be
met. This assumes again that he is
genuinely the initiator and motivating force of the action, not merely a
bureaucrat providing formal approval.
Yet it would seem that a political leader can clearly count as an
unjust, imminent aggressor, at least under some circumstances – hence a
targeted killing could in principle be permissible.
Nonetheless, there remain
serious concerns about the idea of assassination even if we decide that the
target is a combatant; these concerns apply to the assassination of military
leaders as well as political leaders.
First, the fact of premeditation is troublesome; self-defense is
paradigmatically not premeditated, but as Webster describes it, an immediate
reaction where there is no time for deliberation. Second, a primary moral duty under the
doctrine of self-defense is to use the minimum necessary harm. An assassination order, or a bounty offered
for the target “dead or alive” is in itself not morally permissible, because it
violates this duty. Any planned assassination
must be one in which killing is only a last resort; the order must be capture
alive if at all possible. Morally, we
cannot be indifferent between capturing alive or dead. (Some questions were raised, for example,
about the killing of Hussein’s sons: was every reasonable effort made to
capture them alive?) This is to say, a
premeditated killing is always suspect; the aim must be to capture if at all
possible, and to kill only to prevent him from escaping and carrying out
further harm.[12]
A second concern is the danger
of misuse of the policy. In the course
of public debate over the assassination of Hussein, it was widely reported that
some members of the administration wanted to have Hussein dead, in order to
avoid a trial at which embarrassing revelations might come out about the
connections between the United States and the Hussein regime. Obviously, such an improper motive would
invalidate the moral legitimacy of an otherwise legitimate assassination
attempt on Hussein. Similarly, the initiating
attack on Iraq was clearly an assassination attempt on Hussein, based on
intelligence reports that claimed to identify his whereabouts – yet the
Administration refused to describe the attack as an assassination, but insisted
it was merely a legitimate strike against a “command and control” center. In order to evaluate the ethics of the
action, one must be entirely clear about its underlying motivation.
A third concern is the danger of
the slippery slope: once assassinations are ever permitted, will this undermine
the Just War limits on killing? The
worry here is about breaking down the barrier between legitimate killing in
self-defense or in punishment, versus the sort of illegimate killing of which
terrorism is a prime example, and which can simply be called murder. Assassination, given its premeditated
character, is uncomfortably close to the side of illegitimacy. This is not necessarily a reason to reject
the legitimacy of any assassinations, but it is a reason to reiterate the
strict limitations on the policy. To the
extent a person is in a role distant from the actual aggression itself (i.e. a
supervisory role), there must be a direct connection between him and the acts
of violence. A mere figurehead leader,
as Wingfield suggests, is not a legitimate target, nor ordinarily is a civilian
commander in a democratic state. The
ordinary assumption must be that one may use defensive force only against those
who are the agents threatening imminent, unjust violence. The presumption must be against
assassination, given its resemblance to premeditated killing. It is reserved only for exceptional and
urgent circumstances, and when all other methods have failed; to the extent the
target is a political leader rather than a military one, that provides a
further presumption against assassination.
In Just War Theory, assassination can be seen as at best a last resort.[13]
In conclusion, it appears that
the policy of assassination or targeted killing, though it may be morally
legitimate in certain limited circumstances, must in general be considered
impermissible under the Just War Doctrine.
The principle of respect for human life does not in general allow
premeditated, extrajudicial killings of specific individuals. Only in urgent situations or extreme circumstances,
where there is no other means to avoid a given imminent harm, can
assassinations be permitted. And to the
extent the target is a political rather than a military leader, the presumption
against assassination must be even stronger.
The recent shift in opinion in favor of the use of assassination can be
revealed for what it is: a newly emboldened effort of the Realists and the
Consequentialists to make inroads into the Just War Doctrine. But as much as they have the power of emotion
on their side, moral principle must be the ultimate determinant in the conduct
of war.
NOTES
[1]Article 23b of the Hague Regulations, 1907, prohibits “assassination, proscription, or outlawry of an enemy, or putting a price upon an enemy’s head, as well as offering a reward for an enemy ‘dead or alive.’”
[2]”When Can We Target the Leaders?,” Strategic Review (Spring 2001), p.23. See also Thomas Wingfield, “Taking Aim at Regime Elites,” 22 Md. J. Int’l. L. & Trade 287.
[3]See, e.g. Williams Banks, “Targeted Killing and Assassination: the U.S. Legal Framework,” 37 U.Rich.L.Rev.667, 671 (March 2003).
[4]Cf. Abram Chayes, appearing on Nightline: “If Saddam was out leading his troops and he got killed in the midst of an engagement, well, that’s one thing. But if he is deliberately and selectively targeted, I think that’s another.” (Feb. 4, 1991). Cf. Wingfield p.314, criticizing Chayes’ argument.
[5]Brenda Godfrey, “Authorization to Kill Terrorist Leaders,” 4 San Diego Int’l L. J. 491 (2003).
[6]Note the two distinct errors in this claim: (1) a conflation of self-defense with the punishment-based notions of guilt and innocence, and (2) a misunderstanding of the proportionality constraint as a consequentialist provision.
[7]”On International Law and Nuclear Terrorism,” 24 Ga. J. Int’l & Comp. Law 1, p.33.
[8]Quoted in Godfrey p.496. Realists or quasi-realists continually attempt unconvincingly to assert the demise of the Caroline standard. See Godfrey p. , Beres p. 33.
[9]Wingfield p.314.
[10]”The Moral Argument for a Policy of Assassination,” paper delivered at APA Central Division Meeting, 2003.
[11] Jeffrie Murphy, “The Killing of the Innocent,” in War,
Morality, and the Military Profession (Boulder: Westview Press, 1986),
p.346.
[12]One might argue that the ‘dead or alive’ idea means that the ultimate goal is to get the man, however necessary. Still, it implies an indifference as between the two, even a veiled preference for ‘dead.’ Clearly, the moral rule requires the aim of capturing alive if at all possible.
[13] The Israeli policy of assassination of Hamas terrorist leaders has been defended on the grounds that it is designed to prevent imminent unjust attacks on civilians, and that all reasonable alternatives have been exhausted (including issuing arrest warrants to Palestinian authorities, requesting extradition, etc.). To the extent these claims are true, they might constitute a legitimate case of justifiable assassination.