Just War Theory, Law Enforcement, and Terrorism: A Reflective Equilibrium
LTC Daniel S. Zupan
I once attended a conference at which a philosopher
attempted to justify the war against terrorism, particularly the ongoing war in
I believe that our fears are unfounded and that there are
deep principles that can and do justify and guide our use of force in the war
against terrorism. Just war theory is
not obsolete, and our struggle against terrorism is just. The problems of justification have arisen in
attempting to apply the just war theory template in inappropriate ways. We are engaged in a conflict that
conceptually, in many important respects, resembles law enforcement. But the enemy is so arrayed, armed, and
organized, that the forces and tactics required to combat them make our struggle look like conventional
war. Hence, at times the appropriate
model to understand the situation in a moral sense is the model of domestic law
enforcement; at other times, just war theory is the appropriate model.
I will attempt to articulate a reflective equilibrium
between principles of just war theory and principles of law enforcement. Neither model
– just war or law enforcement –
individually adequately captures the moral reality of the war against
terrorism. But if they are taken
together, using moral insights from both domains, a new and relevant model
emerges that can provide moral guidance in the war against terrorism. The apparent inability of one or the other
model to explain and justify our response to terrorism will cease to be cause
for concern since we will have identified consistent principles, which
correspond with deep principles of justice, to guide our use of force.
Pacifism and the Domestic Analogy
I must make some preliminary remarks about pacifism in
order to explore the underlying principles upon which I believe the
justification for the use of force rests.
A better understanding of these fundamental principles of justification
will in turn establish the legitimacy of the domestic analogy upon which I and
many just war theorists traditionally trade.
The
fundamental problem with pacifism is that it judges all violence to be morally
equivalent, a position that seems implausible, even counterintuitive. Violence itself is a morally neutral
concept. For example, it is
inappropriate to judge a violent, deadly storm in moral terms, or to ascribe
moral characteristics to hyenas in their violent attacks on their prey. What imbue acts of violence with their moral
characteristics are the maxims behind them.
A maxim is a subjective principle of volition. More than mere intent, a maxim captures the
general principle of action that generates specific intentions. One might, for instance, adopt a general
maxim to always protect the innocent.
That maxim is particularized to a specific intention when, say, one
intervenes to protect an elderly person from a mugger. One intends to protect this particular
person. Now compare the mugger’s maxim
with that of the person who comes to the aid of the victim. The criminal has adopted an impermissible
maxim since he intends to coerce another human being, to treat that person as a
mere means, not an end in himself.[1] And suppose the person who protects the old
person has to use force; suppose he has to wrestle the mugger to the
ground. Are we to say that the protector’s
use of violence is morally the same as the thug’s violence? This seems implausible and highlights the
untenable nature of the pacifist’s position.
It seems unreasonable to say that appropriate, necessary violence used
to reject evil is of the same moral quality as the evil it rejects.
Of course, there is the pacifist position that condones
violence as it is employed against criminals in domestic society, yet rejects
war as something different not in degree, but kind, from domestic law
enforcement or personal self-defense.
This too seems untenable. If the
ultimate justification for the use of force rests in the rejection of evil, in
defense against those who would use human beings as mere means, then it seems
wrongheaded to reject the just use of violence precisely at the point where
evil has reached an extraordinarily malevolent level. Kant, in The Doctrine of Right, talks about
hindering a hindrance to freedom in justifying the use of force and points out
how there can be instances of justified coercion. Right actions, he says, are those that are
consistent with universal laws of freedom, actions whose universalized maxims are
consistent with free, moral actions of other human beings. Right actions are consistent with a respect
for the dignity of humanity. Unjust
coercion hinders principles that are consistent with universal freedom; hence,
any action that resists that coercion hinders the hindrance and promotes those
principles of freedom. Kant says:
Resistance
that counteracts the hindering of an effect promotes this effect and is
consistent with it. Now whatever is
wrong is a hindrance to freedom in accordance with universal laws. But coercion is a hindrance or resistance to
freedom. Therefore, if a certain use of
freedom is itself a hindrance to freedom in accordance with universal laws
(i.e., wrong), coercion that is opposed to this (as a hindering of a hindrance to freedom) is consistent with freedom in
accordance with universal laws, that is, it is right. Hence there is connected with right by the
principle of contradiction an authorization to coerce someone who infringes
upon it.[2]
Just coercion, the just use
of violence, promotes freedom: this
reasoning is logically, as well as normatively, compelling and explains how a
theory that connects unjust acts with coercion can at the same time justify
certain forms of coercion. And, of
course, the maxims behind the various uses of coercion provide the grounds for
their commendation or condemnation.
If the above account is plausible, it will help justify
the applicability of the domestic analogy to just war theory in general and to
the case at hand in particular. Michael
Walzer says:
The
comparison of international to civil order is crucial to the theory of
aggression…Every reference to aggression as the international equivalent of
armed robbery or murder, and every comparison of home and country or of
personal liberty and political independence, relies upon what is called the domestic analogy. Our primary perceptions and judgments of
aggression are the products of analogical reasoning. When the analogy is made explicit…the world
of states takes on the shape of a political society the character of which is
entirely accessible through such notions as crime and punishment, self-defense,
law enforcement, and so on.[3]
As Walzer points out, just
war theory owes much of its moral force to analogical reasoning about domestic
law enforcement. But there is a
notorious point of disanalogy, namely, that there are no world sovereign and no
world police force. Hence it is often
considered difficult, even illegitimate, to traffic back and forth between the
two domains in attempting to resolve the more intractable problems we face
concerning the use of force, particularly in the international arena. I contend that despite the points of
disanalogy between the international and civil realms, between war fighting and
law enforcement, the justification to use force in either realm follows from deep
moral principles, having to do with resistance to unjust coercion, that transcend
the civil/international distinction. As
such, the pursuit of a reflective equilibrium to justify our response to
terrorism is an eminently legitimate endeavor aimed at illuminating those
shared principles.
Just war theory (JWT) is typically considered from three
perspectives: jus ad bellum, jus in
In terms of JWT, the focus of this paper is jus ad bellum. As I stated, jus post bellum concerns will be examined in the context of jus ad bellum. Jus in
There
are several ways to articulate the various components of jus ad bellum. I will
discuss the following: just cause, right intention, proper
authority, reasonable chance of success, no precipitous use of force (last
resort), proportionality, and just termination.[4] In the discussion of each of them, I will
examine their applicability to the war on terrorism, incorporating insights
from domestic law enforcement, in order to arrive at a coherent, satisfactory,
and morally compelling understanding of the war on terrorism.
I
understand that the war on terrorism takes many forms. My focus here is the on-going war in
Just cause. Defense against aggression represents the
paradigm of just cause to use force.
When one nation invades another, unprovoked, absent an offense to be
redressed, the invaded nation can use force to defend itself. As we have seen in the Walzer passage above,
we understand this insight in terms of the domestic analogy. The relationship obtaining between states is analogous
to that obtaining between individuals within states; both states and
individuals are considered in this context to be rights-bearing agents, and
nations have the right to political sovereignty and territorial integrity. Any violation of these rights in the
international sphere is analogous to robbery or murder in the domestic sphere. Brian Orend says:
The
key principle here is the defence and vindication of fundamental rights, and
the protection of those who have them from serious harm. From these general considerations, three just
causes, in particular, can be deduced:
1) self-defence from aggression; 2) the defence of others from
aggression; and 3) armed intervention in a non-aggressive country wherein
grievous human rights violations are occurring.[5]
There is a presumption that the use of force
against such threats is justified. In
general, we have just cause to use force in self-defense, to protect the
innocent, and to vindicate human rights:
we do all of these in our fight against terrorism.
In the case of terrorism, the
But
the incursion into
There
is another aspect of the issue that we should discuss under just cause. Some contend that the terrorists have
legitimate grievances. But even if we were
to grant the accuracy of that claim, their actions could not be justified. If they claim to be redressing an injustice,
then they are logically committed to our world of moral discourse, and their
position becomes self-defeating. It is
contradictory, in order to attain their ends, to violate justice in the name of
justice.[6] On the other hand, if they don’t accept such
moral terms or even refuse to invoke the cause of justice, their position seems
to reduce to nihilism, an anarchical rejection of anything but the rule of
violence. And if this is the case, they
have no grounds upon which to complain about our campaign against them. Such a complaint on their part reduces to a
sort of absurdity since they would be complaining on the grounds of a normative
standard the existence of which they deny.
It is worth noting that societies always contend with criminals who
either justify their own crimes or deny the validity of the social norms that
condemn their crimes. So this phenomenon
is not unique to terrorism. And in both
domestic and international contexts, principles of justice permit, sometimes
demand, a violent response against those who victimize the innocent.
The principle of just cause, then, seems to work in very
similar ways in both just war theory and law enforcement. In both arenas, just cause derives from
notions of human dignity. We are justified
in rejecting actions that coerce human beings and treat then as mere means; we
are sometimes justified in using force in the defense of human rights.
Right Intention. Even if we have just cause, we
cannot use it as a cloak for other aims.
For example, it would be impermissible to use our legitimate claim of
just cause for attacking Al Qaida (as a war of self-defense or law enforcement)
as a cloak to hide another intention, say, the eradication of the opium
trade. If the latter did provide just cause
in itself, it would have to be justified independently (an unlikely prospect).
This
principle includes the requirement to abide by jus in
In
some way, right intention and just cause are two sides of the same conceptual
coin. To have a right intention is to be
committed to vindicating human rights, rejecting evil, and abiding by the terms
of the justice that warranted our violent response to evil in the first place.
Proper Authority. This is an oft cited yet little
understood principle of just war, and it holds great importance for our
understanding of the fight against terrorism.
On some level, we could view this principle as fundamental to civil or
international order. This principle addresses
issues concerning the legitimate authority to declare and wage war. It is generally acknowledged that only viable
political communities, in the person or persons of their leaders, can
legitimately declare and prosecute war.
The reasons for this provide a critical insight concerning the essential
criminality of terrorism.[8]
I
will borrow an insight from social contract theory. In the state of nature, everyone is empowered
to enforce the law of nature. Once the
community is formed, however, the power of enforcement is transferred to the
body politic and the peoples’ representatives who have been designated to
perform the law enforcement function.
Except under extreme circumstances, ordinary citizens are precluded from
law enforcement activities. A fortiori, they are prohibited from
mounting personal violent campaigns against states. Those who transgress this prohibition or
don’t acknowledge its force, remain in the state of nature with respect to
everyone else. Hence, the rationale
behind this principle is sine qua non
to the possibility of civil and international society. Those who prosecute “private wars” put
themselves in the state of nature with respect to all of humanity. And we should specify that this is a
Hobbesian state of nature, a lawless, anarchical state where the very concepts
of morality, justice, and injustice do not exist.
Terrorists proclaim by their actions their unwillingness
to abide by any laws or social conventions.
They recognize no proscriptions or constraints, or any authority over
them such that it would bind them as members of communities committed to a
cooperative quest for justice. Their
cause, to them, dictates the meaning of justice, or even denies the meaning of
the term. The struggle against them is
in this respect like domestic law enforcement against depraved, violent
criminals who violate state law.[9] Understanding this conceptual framework
properly will pay big dividends as we investigate the connection of just war
concepts to the war against terrorism.
Terrorists represent a rejection of community. In a very deep sense, their ideology is
logically incompatible with the idea of a cooperative human venture, either in
its civil or international forms. It is
not simply that they do not act under the aegis of proper authority, they deny
the relevance of the principle. In so
doing, they deny the legitimacy of states, they deny the rights of people to
carve out a shared life, they deny the unique importance of individual human
beings, and ultimately they deny morality.
They really are like Locke’s savage beasts, predators with whom
coexistence is unthinkable.
This just war principle includes the
following requirement (an insight which again I borrow from Brian Orend). A country engaged in a just war must remain
committed to maintaining and securing the civil liberties of its own citizens. For instance, we witnessed an alarming call
for the curtailment of civil liberties in the
Reasonable chance of success. In
the context of just war, this principle enjoins nations to decline the resort
to war when it seems clear that the effort would be futile. For example, a small nation invaded by an overwhelmingly
superior force should not resort to war.
To resort to war with no chance of success manifests gross indifference
to the lives of those who would die in the futile effort, an effort whose
result is foreseen. It represents a
waste of human lives and a decadent abuse of power by those who frivolously
spend the precious national resource that the citizenry is. For nations faced with this trying situation,
there at least remains hope of diplomatic resolution some time in the future;
but for those wasted dead, all hope is lost.
Although capitulation to evil violates our sense of justice on one
level, complicity in senseless slaughter is a far deeper violation of justice.
However,
there is one circumstance where, even in the face of certain defeat, resistance
might nonetheless be preferable to standing by and doing nothing. If the invading force represents a certain
level of evil and malevolence, such that life under them would be nightmarish,
a fate worse than death, then it might be best to resist. If death or enslavement is inevitable whether
you resist or not, it seems best to resist.
Such resistance might be consistent with respect for humanity and
represent consent on the part of the citizenry, since all would reasonably be
assumed to prefer to fight and die rather than live such an existence. The Nazis represent the sort of evil that
might warrant such a response. That is,
when one faces the same fate either way, it seems at least permissible, if not
preferable, to resist with force. The
heroic actions of the passengers who resisted the highjackers on 9/11 and
prevented an attack on the White House come to mind. They faced death no matter what, so they
fought back. This is not futile effort,
but rather heroic action.
This principle comes to bear on the war against terrorism
in the following way. There are those
who say that we have no reasonable chance of success in eliminating terrorism;
hence, they argue, we shouldn’t take up the fight. Or they argue about the difficulty in
identifying an endstate, which problem at least causes hesitation. But the confusion here arises because detractors
are trying to apply this just war concept to a problem that is much better
understood in terms of the law enforcement model. Consider it this way. We can never reasonably hope to eliminate
robbery or murder. Does it then follow
that we shouldn’t pursue and bring to justice this particular robber or this
murderer? It seems implausible to think
so; we endeavor to bring to justice all evil doers even in the face of the fact
that evil will nonetheless persist.
We
are forced to reevaluate our conception of what an appropriate endstate would
be. Yes, we’d like to eliminate all
terrorism and bring every terrorist to justice.
But falling short of that does not mean we have failed. I’ll discuss this in detail when I consider
just termination, but for now it suffices to point out that we gain some
measure of success with each terrorist we bring to justice. Furthermore, we are successful if we reduce
the threat, just as domestic law enforcement agencies are successful if they
reduce crime. The notion that success is
intrinsically tied to the unconditional surrender[10] and
the complete eradication of the enemy is as inappropriate in this war as it is
in most conventional wars. Justice is met,
perhaps only met, when less comprehensive conditions are set.
A
conceptual error results if we don’t seek the reflective equilibrium. If we follow this line of analysis, we will
develop some reasoned principles to guide us in non-arbitrary ways in conducting
a just campaign against terrorism.
No precipitous use of force. Just war
literature often refers to this principle as “last resort”; it requires nations
to resort to war only as a last resort to resolve problems. But to call it last resort is problematic. Hence, I prefer (following Brian Orend again)
to capture the essence of this principle in terms of the precipitous use of
force. The principle conceived under the
description of last resort is not very helpful in war or in law
enforcement. For one thing, we can never
know what constitutes lastness, as Michael Walzer implies[11]. There always will be one more negotiating
session or one more concession that we can make. Furthermore, by waiting for the so-called
conditions of last resort, we might unwittingly concede the victory to the
enemy. Witness the war in Kosovo. The longer NATO refrained from the resort to
force, the longer the Serbs had to commit their ethnic cleansing. We could argue that, under these
circumstances, justice demands a resort to force sooner rather than later.
What
is required, then, is for nations to consider judiciously the circumstances and
certainly seek peaceful resolution before any resort to war. On the other hand, nations should recognize
that hesitancy to use force in the face of certain forms of evil fails the test
of justice as much as the unnecessary, precipitous use of force. Consider an example in law enforcement. If a criminal is engaged in harming his
victim, we don’t require the police to first negotiate with the criminal to
have him stop. The “last resort”
criterion doesn’t come to bear here in the same way as it does in the arena of
conventional war. The immediacy of the situation
and the unambiguousness of the evil intent/action minimize or eliminate the
requirement for lastness. Of course, if
the police can get the criminal to cease and desist by simply yelling “halt” or
some such thing, we would call for such a course of action. It is circumstance dependent; we could make
the same point about circumstance with respect to war. But in the case of law enforcement, the
presumption in favor of using force is different than that in the case of war. We recognize the exigencies involved with hot pursuit and don’t impose last resort
requirements under such conditions.
Perhaps we feel that we’ve already met the last resort requirement when
involved in hot pursuit against a criminal who is presently engaged in
harming. But that is only to recognize
that negotiations, the use of measures other than force, are sometimes not
appropriate; indeed, they are sometimes impossible unless one sacrifices the
victim.
So
when we have been criticized for having resorted to force too precipitously in
our struggle against terrorism (and we have – I’ve heard the claim made with
respect to the current conflict in
Proportionality. I am going to approach the
issue of proportionality a little differently than the other criteria and offer
a perspective somewhat different than that encountered in much of just war
orthodoxy. In the end, my discussion
suggests at least the plausibility of eliminating proportionality as a just war
criterion. I must begin with its jus in
In the context of just war theory or law enforcement,
proportionality must be considered a normative, not a descriptive term. It can’t be about numbers and ratios of
forces, otherwise we’d get absurd results.
If we are justified in using force to resist evil, we are justified in
using as much force as necessary to win, as long as we don’t ourselves commit
evil in the process. And since at least
part of what is impermissible with the evil we are facing, especially when
facing a violent criminal or conducting a war, is that it coerces us to face
the risk of bodily harm or death, then it is permissible for us to do not only
what is necessary to win, but also what is necessary to reduce our risk to the
bare minimum.[13] Hence, we are morally permitted to achieve
overwhelming force, if possible. That
is, when we resist a threat, say a criminal who attacks us, our just end is to
eliminate that threat. It can’t be the
case, then, that we are morally required to endure risk proportional to the
amount we seek to impose on the criminal, as if he is entitled to fair odds.
Hence, we are not restricted to the use of means proportionate to those
available to our attacker. We may use a
bigger stick than he does, for example, and we may enlist help from as many
people as are available and willing to aid us.
This does not mean that we are permitted to do
whatever would be required to secure victory or reduce risk. When facing our attacker, we can’t snatch a
baby out of the arms of a bystander and use it as a shield. Furthermore, once we have subdued the criminal,
once he can no longer threaten us, we are no longer permitted to harm him – we
can’t beat him or abuse him, although we can continue to restrain him, put him
in jail, and bring him to trial.
Consider a scenario from domestic law enforcement. Suppose a drunkard is causing a disturbance
in a public place, starting fights and attacking people. When the police are called, do we feel their
response is disproportionate when they arrive with several officers to subdue
the man? Hardly. We do not expect the police officers to fight
a “fair fight” and go one-on-one with the criminal just in order to meet some
bizarre proportionality requirement. It
doesn’t matter if they surround him with 100 police officers; no rights of the
criminal will have been violated simply by the force of numbers. His being gravely outnumbered does him no
injustice. He is committing a crime, and
it is permissible to stop him. And that
is the appropriate, permissible goal of the officers. They can subdue the criminal and use force if
required.
But simply granting this obvious point does not resolve
the more complicated issues about proportionality. It still seems to make sense to say that even
if we allow the police to greatly outnumber the criminal, their response must
be proportionate. If they must beat the
criminal, they must stop beating him once he is subdued. Moreover, they must not beat him more
severely than is required to subdue him, and this latter seems to be a
requirement for proportionality and is the most pressing problem we must solve.[14] There is an important sense in which we feel
that the punishment must “fit” the crime and that even the means of enforcement
must be proportionate to the offense. We
ought not incarcerate jaywalkers for life, nor should police shoot people for
spitting on the sidewalk. Such draconian
measures would be condemned as disproportionate.
Deeper analysis will give us a different understanding of
proportionality. My primary target here
is the conception of proportionality as a tradeoff of goods and evils,
especially with regard to the use of force in the domestic or international
arenas. Typically, when we demand
proportionate force, we demand that the good outweigh the evil, as if an evil
component were necessarily connected to the use of force. This is what I object to as incoherent and as
having disastrous moral results if reasoned to its logical conclusion. Look more closely at a domestic scenario. We don’t judge the use of force against a
criminal along a spectrum, with good and evil on its opposite ends vying for
preeminence in one and the same act of violence, both intimately involved. The act’s moral character is not defined
arbitrarily according to the amount of good or evil produced, as if somewhere
along the spectrum a mysterious transmogrification takes place, changing good
into evil. Kant makes a similar point
when decrying the shortcomings of virtue ethics:
…it
is the most objectionable because it bases morality on incentives that
undermine it and destroy all its sublimity, since they put motives to virtue
and those to vice in one class and only teach us to calculate better, but quite
obliterate the specific difference between virtue and vice.[15]
When a police officer
struggles with a criminal, it doesn’t make sense to say that he is doing
something that is both good and evil but that we condone his use of force
because the good outweighs the evil. He
is doing something right in hindering a hindrance. We don’t judge him on a scale. On the other hand, if he shoots the jaywalker
or continues to beat the criminal after the criminal is subdued, we don’t think
that his use of violence is wrong because the evil is now outweighing the
good. Rather, we feel he is simply doing
something evil in its own right. It is not
evil because it is disproportionate; to think so reverses the causal order of
our judgment. I contend that our judgment that such an act (i.e., shooting the
jaywalker) is evil is prior to our designation of it as disproportionate and is
based on principles that form the general grounds for the justification to use
any force whatsoever. Putative
violations of proportionality violate more fundamental rights. Recall that the only justification for the
resort to force in the first place is to hinder a hindrance. It is beyond the scope of this paper to
derive every principle that would follow from this mandate as its ground, but
we can see the direction we might take.
For instance, once he is subdued, it is impermissible to continue to
beat the criminal. This impermissibility
would seem to follow because it would be difficult to argue that one were
hindering a hindrance once the criminal is no longer capable of being a
hindrance. Again, I will not work out
all the principles here, but it should be clear that judgments about the
legitimate use of force are based on notions more fundamental than
proportionality. Once a particular
threat is thwarted, no further warrants follow – less, of course, those that
follow from civil codes having to do with appropriate punishment for
transgressions.[16] But these are all meted out within the
context of the criminal’s being a rights bearing agent in spite of his crimes
and thus protected from the sort of unjust
coercion that police brutality represents.
Given the foregoing discussion, we can see that jus in
Note that this conception of proportionality coincides
well with our more considered judgments about just war and the purpose of the
laws of war. We fight a just war to
safeguard human rights and protect the innocent (we are all of us – even
soldiers -- considered “innocents” until coerced by aggression to defend
ourselves). The rights we uphold, the
people we defend, impose the moral limits we must follow. Once we see that our use of force is not
inevitably a tradeoff of good for evil, we will see the inherent evil in some
actions, say, the deliberate targeting of noncombatants, and will be prohibited
from taking such actions. The very
rights that justify our violent response in the first place impose the moral
limits on the violence we use.[17] This understanding of the status of rights
might be one of the most important results of this analysis of
proportionality. We rule out in advance
the notion that we can do evil to prevent evil, as if somehow the real blood of
the few innocents whom we deliberately kill can be washed from our hands by the
imagined blood of the many innocents we allegedly save.
In terms of jus ad
bellum, proportionality traditionally plays out in two ways. First, nations must consider whether the
resort to war for a given offense is a proportionate response. Not every violation of territorial integrity
or political sovereignty constitutes aggression; hence, not every such
violation justifies war as a response.
We wouldn’t be justified in going to war against
The second way in which proportionality is said to figure
in just war analysis has to do with the weighing of consequences. As Orend writes:
A
state must, prior to initiating a war, weigh the expected universal good to
accrue from its prosecuting the (otherwise just) war against the universal
evils expected to result. Only if the
benefits, such as rights vindication, seem reasonably proportional to the
costs, such as casualties, may the war action proceed.[18]
I believe this is a
conceptual error. Again, it makes it
appear as if there is something intrinsically evil in the recourse to war, as
if we must admit that dirty hands are somehow inescapable on the part of those
who would resist aggression with force. As we have seen, the domestic analogy
provides some insight as to the inadequacy of this conception of
proportionality.
There
is nothing inherently evil with the policeman’s doing of his duty. We
don’t think that there is an evil aspect of his use of force against the
criminal that is justified only if outweighed by the good results. In the terms of this discussion, the
policeman has adopted a permissible maxim – in itself there is no evil
aspect. This is not to say that no
action on his part could be impermissible.
For example, it would be impermissible for him to throw a baby in front
of the vehicle of an escaping criminal in an attempt to get the criminal to
stop. But this course of action is ruled
out because it is so grossly rights violative; it is not an issue of proportionality. The policeman has been commissioned to
protect the innocent, and this commission imposes the just limits on the
actions he can take. He must not hurt
the innocent in the pursuit of the guilty; he must not violate justice in the
name of justice.
It
is the protection of rights that imposes limits, not a principle of
proportion. When we view the underlying
principles that justify our resistance to evil in the first place, we see that
justification is not based on principles of proportionality but rather on
principles of human rights. We are
committed to rejecting unjust coercion and must eschew means that themselves
violate the principles in whose name we act.
We
must consider the enterprise of war in a similar light. We should not consider it as an inherently
unjust endeavor for the same reasoning as we reject such a conception of the
situation in the domestic sphere. When
coerced to protect ourselves, using force against evil, it is inaccurate to
characterize our use of force as involving an inherent aspect of evil. Furthermore, if we were to conceive our
enterprise as in some respects evil, it could permit the contemplation of
actions that violate the principles of justice that warranted our violent
response: we would, in the end, involve
ourselves in a contradiction.
It
is not the case, then, that police brutality or wartime atrocities are
condemned on the grounds that they are disproportionate. What we’ll find, ultimately, is that actions
that have historically been condemned as disproportionate have in fact violated
other principles. And if my account is
correct, we might consider dropping proportionality as a standard just war
criterion.
Just termination. If we invoke the cause of
justice as our reason for going to war, then justice itself must dictate the
desired endstate. This endstate
specifies both what must be attained in order for justice to be met, and it
specifies limitations on what can be done in order to remain within the
limitations imposed by considerations of justice. Domestic law enforcement provides a helpful
model for understanding the requirements of this principle with respect to the
war on terrorism.
In
some sense, the struggle will never end, in the same way that in domestic
society we will always face criminal threats and will always seek to prevent
crime and to bring criminals to justice.
The conditions for the termination of the struggle and all that it
entails will probably never be met.
Nonetheless, we recognize that just societies seek a balance between
order and civil liberty. So against the
backdrop of a ceaseless struggle against evil, we recognize limits imposed by
justice. We recognize that we must have
limited aims lest we sacrifice the very rights and freedoms we fight to
protect.
Given an awareness of the ubiquity of evil, we adopt
reasonable ends. We do so in domestic
society, and we must do so in the international arena. And with respect to the war on terrorism,
since there is no world police force, we must recognize the limitations imposed
on us by the political sovereignty and territorial integrity of nations. We can’t have carte blanc law enforcement
powers in other nations. For instance,
even though there will be Al Qaida and Taliban fighters in Afghanistan for the
foreseeable future, we do not have the prima facie right simply on that account
to continue to occupy Afghanistan indefinitely.
What seems appropriate is that we have the right to eliminate enough of
the terrorists and their infrastructure to attain a certain level of
security. Furthermore, we are permitted
to stay until a viable government, capable of law enforcement, emerges.
That
we should be able to occupy a country until it can maintain order within its borders follows from what it means
to be politically sovereign or to enjoy territorial integrity. It does not seem appropriate to ascribe full sovereignty
to a people who cannot maintain any viable government, cannot impose any law
and order within its borders, and cannot control in any way the integrity of
its own borders. But once sovereignty in
a meaningful way is attained by the country in question, for an intervening
power to stay longer in the pursuit of an unattainable goal, say the complete
elimination of the threat, is both foolhardy and unjust.
On the other hand, we would be equally foolhardy and
unjust to leave too early. If we leave
before the threat is reduced sufficiently enough for the people of Afghanistan
to autonomously police their own country, we open them up to reprisals and
repression at the hands of the criminal element we are attempting to bring to
justice. We also leave the world no more
secure than when we embarked on the endeavor.
Finally, any soldiers who might have died during the conflict might be
said to have died in vain. There are
certain minimal goals that must be attained for us to have met the demands of
justice. There is a sense where the
struggle is validated and our cause vindicated only if we accomplish, insofar
as it remains possible to accomplish, the goal we set out to do.
The
domestic analogy provides a useful model.
A police officer who merely chases a criminal away from his (the
criminal’s) victim and does nothing more would be remiss. Certainly he has done his job in protecting
the victim, but that is only the beginning of his duties. We expect pursuit. If he cannot apprehend the criminal at the
time, we expect an investigation. We
expect a reasonable attempt to bring the criminal to justice because that is
what ultimately leads to greater crime prevention. To extend the analogy a little further, suppose
the criminal kills a police officer during the chase. If we maintain no commitment to apprehend the
assailant, we devalue the life of the policeman; his death was in vain. We must take up the fight where he left off,
confirming that we share in the conviction that the values he had defended are
worth the sacrifice. It can’t be the
case that the values are only worth his
sacrifice; they must be worth our
sacrifice.[19] We must show that we are willing to make the
same sacrifice, that he is the representative of a collective commitment to
justice; we are partners in a collective venture, all equally committed to the
same goals.
In a
larger sense, then, the demands of justice can’t be episodic. By this I mean that to recognize the demands
of justice and insist on their prescriptivity is to be committed to bearing the
burdens that come with the resistance to evil.
Enforcement by exception, prosecution as mere expedience, is not
justice. The very logic of the concept
of justice implies a coherent system of rules and rights, enforced and
protected in consistent ways by people and institutions that exist as testimony
to the recognition that there is a cost to bear and values worth bearing
it. Accordingly, we who would pursue
terrorists across the globe must be committed to bearing the cost implicit in
attaining a state characterized by the relative absence of terrorism. We seek a world community wherein this crime
is under control and wherein mechanisms are in place to prevent its wholesale
reemergence and to prosecute the transgressors.
The requirements of just termination in the war against
terrorism are different from those in conventional war in another respect. We might envision a typical conventional war
scenario where two belligerent sides meet at a negotiating table and hammer out
the conditions of surrender. The
defeated side agrees to give up certain activities and accept certain
conditions in return for a cessation of hostilities. At the same time, it makes certain demands
before it will accept the terms of surrender. The victorious side in turn makes
certain concessions to its enemy so that the fighting might end. A settlement is sought in terms of
justice. Very seldom is unconditional
surrender demanded; rarer yet is it morally permissible. In the case of terrorism, this scenario is
not typical, although clearly it is not unprecedented. The British have negotiated with the IRA, the
Israelis with the PLO, etc. In any case,
the important point for the current struggle is that it is hard to imagine what
terms of justice could be agreed upon by the competing sides. If we conceive of terrorists as criminals,
not soldiers acting on behalf of a legitimate state, we see the
inappropriateness of seeking a resolution strictly along these just war lines. What activities would criminals agree to give
up? They are already committed to
violating justice, so what conditions of justice could we reasonably expect
them to accept? The point is that room
for negotiation here seems so narrowly limited as to be nonexistent. Since their activity is inherently criminal
and unjust, we want them to give up that. About that there can be no negotiations. They are in the state of nature with respect
to the rest of society and must be dealt with on those terms.
Any settlement with the terrorists would be wholly
coercive by nature. By this I mean that
there is no question of the terrorists’ putting forth demands we must accept in
the name of justice as reasonable grounds for them to stop; that is, there are
no just demands they could have, the nonsatisfaction of which would justify
their continued criminal activity. As police coerce the criminal to subdue him,
so do nations coerce terrorists to stop them.
We don’t consider that there are
certain conditions a murderer is justified in demanding be met before he ceases
to commit murder. To think that the
failure to meet certain of his demands justifies his continued reign of terror
is, quite simply, to make the logical error that justice demands that he continue
violating justice, an absurdity.
Although I have already rejected the notion of
unconditional surrender, there is a sense where such a demand is morally
relevant. From the moral perspective,
each response to terrorism is a demand for unconditional surrender, at least
metaphorically. We cannot morally or
prudentially concede the legitimacy of terrorism under any conditions. Each encounter with terrorists is like the
policeman’s encounter with the murderer.
The activity of terror or murder is inherently unjust such that the terrorist
(or murderer) must cease it unconditionally; no demand he could make in
negotiation could in any way justify his continued murderous activity should we
fail to meet the demand. This is not to
say that the terrorist forfeits all his rights, even though, metaphorically, we
demand his unconditional surrender.
Recall that we demand the same of criminals; yet, once they surrender,
they gain certain rights under the law.[20] Hence, the terrorists, as criminals, would acquire
legal rights. They might be considered
innocent until proven guilty, for example.
But these rights are rendered within a context that nonetheless
unconditionally condemns the crime.
There is no question that we have negotiated a settlement about the
legitimacy of the activity. We have
condemned it categorically and now are affording the suspects the right to
prove that they are innocent of an act that remains a crime. If they are found guilty, negotiations in the
relevant sense (less plea bargaining, for example) will not ensue.
Terrorism is a menace that shall not soon leave us. It threatens our lives in pervasive
ways. Such a threat assails even our
moral bulwarks; and it is at times of gravest extremity when we must most
zealously guard and cherish our integrity.
For in the end it is our integrity that is under the severest
assault. We face a challenge of our
deepest values, and we cannot capitulate in the face of such moral
coercion. So I have fired a volley in
defense of our profoundest human ideals, offering a conceptual apparatus that
both explains and proves legitimate our deep intuitions about the justness of
our response against this most heinous of evils. My hope is that a clearer understanding of
the moral reality of the war against terrorism will yield consistently
appropriate and ethical responses to this plague upon humanity.
NOTES
[1] What it is to treat someone as a mere means is not as easy to understand as some might mistakenly assume. Nonetheless, for the purposes of this paper, it is sufficient to say that we treat someone as a means if we treat him in ways to which he could not possibly consent. Lying to someone, robbing him, or murdering him are paradigms of treating someone as a means. In general, such actions are inconsistent with the respect people are owed in virtue of the dignity they possess as human beings.
[2] Immanuel
Kant, The Metaphysics of Morals, ed.
Mary Gregor (Cambridge University Press, 1996), 6: 231.
[3] Michael
Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars: A Moral Argument with Historical
Illustrations, 3rd ed (Basic Books, 1977), p. 58.
[4] I borrow
much of this particular list from Brian Orend’s work, War and International Justice: A
Kantian Perspective. Furthermore,
much of the discussion follows his insightful approach to the issues. Anyone with a serious interest in just war
theory should read Orend’s excellent book.
[5] Orend, p. 268.
[6] Clearly I am rejecting any consequentialist reasoning here. It is not within the scope of this paper to provide a rejection of consequentialism. I assume the appropriateness of the Kantian approach. Furthermore, just war theory and domestic law both seem to embrace the notion that justice itself imposes limits on what can be done in justice’s pursuit. And in many respects, human rights ground the dominant conception of justice such that we are precluded from violating human rights in order to promote them.
[7] I follow Brian Orend in this discussion. His way of elaborating the issue is very insightful, helpful, and clear.
[8] Some might think we trivialize the evil of terrorism by characterizing it in terms of criminal activity. But there are crimes of varying degrees of malevolence, and terrorism resides on the very limits of the spectrum of evil. Furthermore, the criminal model is most appropriate for our conceptual analysis.
[9] An important just war concept is the moral equality of soldiers. As long as they are fighting justly, obeying the laws of war, soldiers on all sides of a conflict are considered moral equals, fighting for their own country (a proper authority) in a cause they think is just. That is why they are given POW rights if captured and repatriated after a war. Terrorists are not considered moral equals with those who combat them, anymore than the criminal in a shootout is considered a moral equal of the policeman trying to apprehend him. This insight further reinforces the appropriateness of the law enforcement model in understanding certain aspects of the war against terrorism.
[10] Just
war theory generally rejects as unjust any demand for unconditional surrender
as being violative of the political sovereignty of a people. Except against a Nazi-like nation, the just
goals of war must be more modest. See
Walzer’s excellent discussion, Just and
Unjust Wars, esp. pp. 110-17, 266-68.
[11] Ibid, p. 213.
[12] An important point to ponder is that, in many cases, nonviolent responses might be far more morally troubling than violent ones. Consider the evil effects on the Iraqi people of the sanctions that have been imposed on the Iraqi government. The sanctions are indiscriminate, and their effects are more widely felt by the innocent than by the guilty.
[13] We are
resisting a threat to our rights. But
these rights are important because they are human
rights. Hence, the ground of the
justification to use force rests on human rights. When we defend ourselves, we are defending
human rights, which just happen to be our human rights at this particular
time. Understanding the situation this
way – as rights defense, not self-defense, imposes moral limits on what we can
do in defense. We must not, for
instance, violate other human rights to defend ourselves. The next paragraph of the essay provides an
example of what I am getting at here.
[14] I owe this insight to Professor Richard Schoonhoven.
[15]
Immanual Kant, Groundwork of the
Metaphysics of Morals.
[16] There
might be room for a consideration of proportionality when it comes to deciding
punishment for crimes: we want to have
the punishment fit the crime. But it is also possible that some deeper
principle of rights is involved, having to do with the rights of the criminal vis a vis the rights of his victims or
the nature of the societal values he has profaned.
[17] In every war, sadly, noncombatants are injured and killed as the unintentional result of legitimate wartime actions. These unintentional and undesired effects are justified under the Doctrine of Double Effect (DDE). Many theorists include proportionality as a criterion for DDE. I can’t offer a complete account of the doctrine here, but I have argued elsewhere (Autonomy and Noncombatant Immunity: An Investigation in Just War Theory, TBP) that proportionality can and should be dropped from DDE for reasons similar to those I have been developing here. The proportionality criterion ushers in a consequentialist notion that might not be desirable. Furthermore, other principles do the moral work. For instance, a requirement to take due care, as Walzer enjoins (Just and Unjust Wars, p.156), imposes the sought-after moral constraints without opening the door to a tradeoff of lesser evils. Once one allows for the tradeoff, it becomes, in principle, possible to justify the impermissible, say, the deliberate slaughter of noncombatants, as long as the payoff is high enough.
[18] Orend, p. 269.
[19] We should understand that whether or not the soldier’s death is in vain is not tied to victory but to shared commitment. It seems inappropriate to say a soldier has died in vain simply because his country lost the war. If his countrymen shared his cause and fought as long as victory seemed attainable, it might be inaccurate to characterize his death as a futile sacrifice. Of course, the question of futility with respect to mankind’s innumerable wars is more profound than I can address here, and many might take issue with the insight of this footnote.
[20] Perhaps there is the implicit condition that surrender guarantees certain legal rights, as well as protection from torture or summary execution. But even unconditional surrender in war, when it is justified, provides for these minimal protections.