CPT Pete Kilner
Instructor, U.S. Military Academy
Phone: 845-938-4764
Fax: 845-446-2562
E-mail: cp4040@usma.edu
Paper presented to
The Joint Services Conference on Professional Ethics
Washington, DC,
January 25-26, 2001
Updated as of 2/27/01
In this paper, I argue that much of the concern
about the alleged “values gap” and its implications stems from an imprecise use
of language. First, a “culture gap” is
not a “values gap.” In the situation at
hand, the culture gap is a good thing, whereas a values gap might not be. Second, and more significantly, the term
“values” is used equivocally in the
literature and research surrounding this issue. “Values” is used to mean both “moral ideals” and “moral standards
of conduct,” and this equivocation confuses the issue. Once we recognize the two distinct and
different meanings of the term values, we will recognize that there is no gap
in moral ideals, and consequently there is no “impending divorce” between the
military and the society it serves.
There is, however, a gap in the moral standards of conduct in some
areas. This gap is based on the
functional imperatives of the military profession, and it is one that an
educated public would support.
Likewise, the fact that the military community has
its own distinct culture does not necessarily entail that its values differ
from those of civilian society. A
culture gap is significant only if it
leads to a values gap, because it is differences in values that could
destabilize civil-military relations.
So, let us examine the alleged civil-military values gap.
Should we accept this assessment? Are we really on this alarming path? It’s not obvious that we are. After all, we would expect that differences in values between the military and civilians would breed distrust and fear. But it hasn’t. The military remains a very popular and trusted organization, even among those who don’t seem to share its values.
How can this be?
How can we have a values gap without suffering the logical consequences
of a values gap? I have an idea, based
initially on my own experiences at a civilian graduate school, and corroborated
recently by the latest surveys on the values gap. While attending a large state university, I found that although
civilians understand very little about how the military is organized and how it
operates, they do overwhelmingly ascribe positive character traits to military
personnel. Simply because I was an Army
officer, my professors and fellow graduate students clearly expected me to
be—honest, disciplined, respectful, hard-working, drug-free (which was
significant in a philosophy department).
The typical comment I heard was: “I really respect you military people;
I could never do it.” Think about that: “I really respect you military people;
I could never do it.” In other words, we share the same values, even though we
act differently.
This captures the essence of why, although there is
a values gap between the American military profession and civilian society,
this gap is not a problem. We use the
term “values” to mean two very different things. We use it equivocally. We use it to mean both standards of behavior
and ideals of behavior. Those who
lament a values gap use the term to mean “standards.” It’s true. The enforced
professional standards of behavior for the military personnel and for civilians
are different. The military does not
tolerate lying, cheating, adultery, and drunk driving, whereas to a large
extent civilian society does. But there
is another sense of values at work here.
Our values are also our ideals.
There is no gap in the ideals of the American society and the
military. Both groups agree that,
ideally, lying, cheating, adultery, drunk driving, etc. are wrong. In this way, although there may be a gap in
moral standards of behavior, there is no gap in moral ideals.
Now, it is important to note that the military
culture does not enforce high standards of moral behavior for all of the
universally shared moral ideals.
Ideally, stewardship of the environment is good, but no one’s military
career is wrecked by a negligent fuel spill.
Ideally, stewardship of public funds is good, yet that doesn’t stop
units from wasting thousands of dollars at the close of each fiscal year. No, the military culture’s standards of
behavior approach the ideals of human behavior only in those areas that are
necessary for it to perform its role in society.
The professional function of the military is to
defend society by being able to fight and win wars. To do so, it must have leaders who are committed to principles “outside
of themselves.” Military leaders must
be willing to risk their own welfare for the good of others. They must be so trustworthy, and inspire
such confidence in their judgment, that their subordinates are willing to
follow their orders even though it means that they have to kill others and risk
their own death. Certain character
traits—commitment, honesty, selflessness—traits that inspire such trust and
confidence, must be present in military personnel if the military is to
effectively serve society. The values
gap—the gap in moral standards of conduct—is created by the functional demand
for these traits in military leaders.
This is why a society that tends to condone
dishonesty and unfaithfulness among civilians demands honesty and commitment in
its military leaders.
Still, it does seem that society holds the military
to a higher standard. Military
personnel, unlike other professionals, are required to adhere to their
profession-driven, higher moral standards even in their personal lives. Society doesn’t demand such things of
doctors and lawyers. Lawyers are not
disbarred for adultery. As recent
events have shown, as long as someone is doing a good job, society is willing
to overlook character flaws. Why the
higher standard for the military?
The higher standard, I think, is due to the
military’s monopoly power over society.
The American people have only one military; they have no choice. Moreover, the 1.4 million members of the
military act as one organism. To
understand how threatening this could be, imagine this: Imagine that there were
only one accounting firm; it alone calculated our taxes; once it did so, we had
no avenue of appeal; all of its personnel operated as one organism. If that were the case, wouldn’t we demand
that the accounting firm ensure that its CPAs be of high moral character? So, too, with the medical profession. Imagine one big medical practice; all of the
doctors and nurses worked together; we had no choice in our doctor, and no
opportunity for a second opinion. If
the American people were indeed this vulnerable to the whims of the medical
profession, we would no doubt demand that medical personnel be as trustworthy
as possible.
Well, American society is this vulnerable to the
military profession. There is only one
military available; society has no choice.
When it comes time for the military to do its job, society could suffer
greatly if the military is not effective.
Society has no opportunity for a second opinion. In a way unique among professions, the military
represents all the members of society; when it acts, domestically or abroad,
its actions reflect on all Americans.
Given these factors, we should not be surprised that civilian society
attempts to reduce its vulnerability to the military’s monopoly by demanding
that certain moral ideals become the military’s standards of moral behavior.
Before
addressing some recent empirical evidence, allow me to briefly summarize my
argument:
I
assume that there exists a consensus of moral ideals.
I
claim that:
Literature on the values gap fails to distinguish
between values as ideals and values as standards of conduct.
There is not a gap in values
as moral ideals between the military and civilian society.
There is a gap in values as standards of conduct between
the military and civilian society.
Shared ideals will preserve the proper
civil-military relationship.
Further, I claim that the gap in norms is justified
by the demands of the profession.
Finally,
I posit that these demands are uniquely stringent—personally and
professionally—due to the military’s unique monopoly of power. The higher moral
standards reduce civilian vulnerability, thereby preserving the proper
civil-military relationship.
The
studies found that civilian elites and military officers shared views on many
issues:
They both supported women in the
military;
They both strongly supported
personal liberties;
They both strongly supported political freedoms;
They were both equally pessimistic
about the moral health of civilian society;
They both agreed on the role of the
military (relative to non-military institutions) in national security.
Where
did the views of the civilian and military leaders differ?
The civilians showed greater support for women
serving in combat roles;
The civilians held that homosexuals should be
permitted to serve openly in the military, while the military leaders
disagreed.
The civilians disagreed with military officers’
position that a “warrior culture” is good for the military.
When we look at survey results, we will find that the
answers corroborate the thesis that there is no gap in moral ideals. The studies found no gap when the question
involved moral ideals, such as personal and political liberties. A gap appears only in those questions that
involve practical military judgment.
For example, the survey asks the participants if
they support gays and lesbians serving openly in the military. “By a very large
margin (76%), elite military officers oppose gays and lesbians openly serving
in the military. But a majority of civilian elites (55%) and the mass public
(57%) support gays and lesbians openly serving,” noted the report.7
Should this be taken to indicate that there exists a gap in values,
military officers oppose rights for gays?
We cannot know because, unfortunately, the surveys ask questions that
fail to distinguish between values as ideals and values as standards.
To
examine this issue properly, the survey should have asked several questions:
Should gays and lesbians have the right to equal
employment opportunities? [Ideals]
Should the military deny admittance to such persons
(e.g., those who are overweight, visually impaired, mentally retarded,
diabetic, amputees, hemophiliacs, convicted felons, etc.) whose service in the
military would not be cost-effective, whose service would actually become a net
burden on the military? [Ideals]
Does the cohesion among members of a military unit
affect that unit’s military effectiveness? [Judgment]
Would the presence of openly gay and lesbian service
members adversely impact the cohesion of military units in which they serve?
[Judgment]
Which is more important: that the military fight
effectively, or that it allow all citizens who wish to serve the opportunity to
do so? [Ideal]
Do you support gays and lesbians serving openly in the
military? [Ideals + Judgment]
Think
of it this way:
Just as tactics is doctrine applied to a situation,
moral standards are moral ideals applied to a profession. Leaders in different situations will apply
the same doctrine using different tactics; likewise, Americans in different
professions will apply the same, shared moral ideals to arrive at different
moral standards of behavior, which are based on the requirements of their
respective profession. Mere differences in standards of behavior do not necessarily
indicate differences in moral ideals.
Differences in standards of behavior may result from different practical
judgments.
Only when survey questions are framed to distinguish
between values as ideals and values as standards (which involve practical
judgments) will we be able to know if a dangerous values gap does exist. As is, the data corroborates the thesis that
there is no gap in ideals, which in turn helps to explain why the military is
such a respected institution.
a. Future surveys should frame questions in ways that will distinguish between moral ideals, military judgments, and expected moral standards of conduct.
b.
In
order to decrease the “values gap,” military personnel should educate the
civilian population on the military-specific judgments that are responsible for
the gap in moral standards of conduct.8
1 Thomas Ricks, “The Widening Gap Between the Military and Society,” Atlantic Monthly (July 1997): 68.
2 Peter D. Feaver and Richard H. Kohn, “The Gap: Soldiers, Civilians, and their Mutual Misunderstanding,” National Interest” (Fall 2000): 30.
3 This poll result has been consistent for the past decade. See http://www.gallup.com/poll/releases/pr990714.asp for one example.
4 Justice Scalia offered this insight at an address that I attended at the United States Military Academy, West Point, NY, April 2000.
5 Ricks, “The Widening Gap Between the Military and Society,” 74.
6 Feaver and Kohn, “Digest of Findings and Studies, First Revision—June 2000, TISS Project on the Gap Between the Military and Civilian Society,” available at http://www.poli.duke.edu/civmil/
7 ibid., 5.
8 Please email me your comments, questions, or any other feedback.