The
opinions expressed in this essay are the author's and do not necessarily
reflect those of the United States Military Academy, the Department of the
Army, or the Department of Defense.
Unintentional Terrorism?: Some Objections
to Rodin’s “Terrorism without Intention”[1]
Stephen N. Woodside
United States Military Academy
David Rodin defines ‘terrorism’ as
the “deliberate, negligent, or reckless use of force against noncombatants,”[2]
though he concedes that his account “is at odds with the current common usage
of the term.”[3] While most believe that terrorism necessarily
involves the intentional killing of noncombatants (NCs), Rodin disagrees. His definition allows that some acts
involving the unintentional killing of NCs, those that are reckless or
negligent, are acts of terror. And while
he offers some support for his unorthodox definition, Rodin develops a more substantive
argument that “many of the noncombatant casualties caused in the course of
military operations (including those of Western nations)” are unjustified.[4] Furthermore, those responsible for these
casualties, whether or not we ought to call them ‘terrorists’, are morally
blameworthy to the same degree as those who intentionally target the innocent.[5] Rodin’s argument is based on his core premise
that many of the actions involving the foreseeable killing of NCs (call them
“standard cases”[6])
are reckless or negligent despite their satisfying the DDE. He begins his support for this claim by
arguing that the DDE is false, as it does not provide sufficient moral
justification for an action. I will
argue Rodin’s objections to the DDE are unconvincing and that his argument is
unsound primarily because his core premise is false. Furthermore, I will argue that those
responsible for killing NCs in the standard cases are not as morally
blameworthy as those who commit traditional acts of terror (those that intentionally
target the innocent), even if these actions are unjustified.
I. The Doctrine of Double Effect
(DDE).
Rodin’s argument that many of the
standard cases are unjustified begins with his objecting to the doctrine of
double effect (DDE). He claims that an
action’s satisfying the DDE is not sufficient moral justification for it since
the DDE allows that some reckless or negligent actions are morally
permitted. He summarizes the DDE below:
One may never intentionally bring
about an evil, either as an end in itself, or as a means to some greater
good. Nonetheless, one may use neutral
or good means to achieve a good end which one foresees will have evil
consequences provided that (i) the evil consequences are not disproportionate
to the intended good, (ii) the action is necessary in the sense that there is
no less costly way of achieving the good.[7]
Rodin then offers two counterexamples to the DDE:
Take the case of a motorist who
drives across a crowded school yard to deliver a sick person to a
hospital. The motorist certainly has no
direct intention to harm the children—he aims at their death neither as a means
nor as an end. His conduct may be
necessary in the context, and if we imagine that the risk of death to his
passenger and to the children are roughly balanced, then it will also be
proportionate. Yet if he strikes and
kills a child he will be held liable, in law and morality, for manslaughter
because of the recklessness of his actions.
Similarly, a medical researcher who prematurely tests an unsafe new
vaccine on humans out of a desire to speed the development of the product and
thereby save lives is guilty of negligent action and may be liable for
manslaughter. This is true even though
his action may fulfill all the requirements of the double-effect principle.[8]
So according to Rodin, while the actions of the motorist and
medical researcher both satisfy the DDE, they are reckless or negligent, and
therefore, unjustified. The DDE is too
permissive. Rodin believes, therefore,
that we need a better account of what makes these actions, and others like them
in combat, reckless or negligent, and hence, unjustified.[9]
But I find these counterexamples
unconvincing. Let us first consider the
motorist’s actions. If we construct this
case in such a way as to make it clear that it satisfies the DDE, then it is no
longer clear to me that it is unjustified.
And conversely, if we construct it in such a way as to make it clear
that it is unjustified, it then becomes unclear whether or not it satisfies the
DDE. To clarify, let us assume that the
good of the motorist’s saving the sick person outweighs the risk of harm to the
children. His action is
proportionate. But is it really
necessary in the relevant sense? Is
there no less costly way of achieving his good?
Are there not any other equally effective routes for him to travel? Can he not swerve or slow his speed to avoid
the children, or sound his horn to alert them while still achieving his
good? If the answer is “yes” to any of
these, then I agree that his action is unjustified. But in this case, it would fail the necessity
condition of the DDE. But if there
really is no less costly way for the motorist to deliver the sick person, then
I am not convinced that the action is unjustified. The intuition that his action is unjustified
seems forceful only when we imagine the motorist as a marauding daredevil who
disregards any alternative less costly courses of action.[10] What about the medical researcher? While it seems more plausible that his action
is proportionate, necessary, and unjustified, it does not follow from this that
it satisfies the DDE. The medical
researcher’s action fails to satisfy the DDE because the harm that he brings
about is a means to speeding the development of the vaccine and saving future
lives. In my opinion then, neither of
these cases is a convincing counterexample to the DDE. So where does all this leave us with the
DDE? I suggest that the DDE can account
for the reckless and unjust nature of the motorist’s and medical researcher’s
actions in spite of Rodin’s criticisms.
Nevertheless, Rodin believes that there is an additional moral
requirement “which goes beyond the necessity and proportionality requirements,
namely: is it justifiable to inflict such a risk upon this particular person?”[11]
II. Rodin’s Argument.
Continuing with his explanation of the shortcomings of the DDE, Rodin
writes, “The fact that the risks are necessary (from the perspective of the
beneficiaries of the risky activity) and proportionate (from the impersonal
perspective of the world at large) is not sufficient to defeat the personal
right not to be endangered or used in this way.”[12] So an action that satisfies the DDE,
according to Rodin, might still be reckless or negligent, as it might fail to
adhere to the moral requirement “not to undertake unreasonable risks,”[13]
foreseeable risks inflicted upon those who maintain their right not to be
harmed (hereafter “relevant right”). So
if an action results in the foreseeable harming of those who maintain their
relevant right, then it is unreasonable.
And if it is unreasonable, then it is reckless. Finally, if it is reckless, then it is
unjustified.
Now all of
this would imply that any act of war causing foreseeable harm to NCs is
unjustified if there were no way for an NC to surrender his relevant
right. But Rodin thinks that there are
circumstances under which NCs do this.
To explain, he offers three domestic examples in which those facing
foreseeable harm have alienated their
relevant right:
…it may be justified for a surgeon to
perform an operation in which there is an extremely high risk of death to the
patient, if the alternative surgery is an even higher risk of death or of great
suffering. Moreover, police cars and
ambulances are permitted to exceed the speed limit and pass red lights in
emergencies (though of course strict requirements of care remain, e.g., the
requirement to display warning lights, the requirement to slow down when
entering intersections, and the requirement to generally minimize the risk to
others). Finally, road engineers are
permitted to make a reasonable trade-off between cost and safety when designing
a road, though they know that this will lead to a certain number of otherwise
avoidable fatalities.[14]
Rodin argues that “in all the above examples a crucial part
of what makes the risk justifiable is that the party assuming the risk is also
the beneficiary of the risk-producing activity,” and “one may rightly say that
the community which enjoys the benefits of improved apprehension of criminals
and an affordable road system also bears the risks incurred.”[15] And although this is an important part of
requirement for the surrender of one’s relevant right, Rodin suggests that more
is required:
[The alienation of the relevant right] links
to the idea of autonomous agency and free acceptance of risk. A patient decides whether to assume the risk
profile of a given operation and every community makes its own collective
decision about how to make the trade-offs involved in building roads and
apprehending criminals. The risks are
justifiable in these cases, at least in part, because they have been
autonomously assumed either individually or collectively by those who bear
them.[16]
But while Rodin thinks that some NCs do surrender their
relevant right in similar ways, he believes that no such surrender takes place
in the standard cases. Before we proceed
any further, let us consider the following standard case (call it “A1”):
A1: An American pilot drops a smart bomb on a known terrorist training
camp that is set in the middle of a highly populated residential area. The pilot drops this bomb to eliminate the
terrorist threat to both the local populace and his own ground troops, as the
terrorists frequently target both of these groups. Based on his experience with these types of
munitions, the pilot foresees that his action will cause 50-100 NC casualties,
but he does not intend for this to happen, nor is his harming these civilians a
means to eliminating the terrorist camp.
Furthermore, the good of his destroying the terrorist camp far outweighs
the harming of these civilians. Finally,
his dropping the bomb is necessary in the sense that there is no less costly
way of achieving his intended good. His
action satisfies the DDE.
Do the NCs harmed in A1 surrender their relevant right? Rodin argues that they do not:
In standard cases of military
conflict [like A1] there is no sense in which the party who bears the risk of
harm benefits from the risky activity.
Neither have they autonomously chosen, either individually or
collectively, to bear the risks of the bombardment. It is extremely doubtful, therefore, whether
the risks imposed on enemy NCs [in A1] can be justified in an analogous way to
the risks imposed in domestic emergency situations.[17]
So according to Rodin, an NC alienates his relevant right
only if (i) he stands to benefit (either individually or collectively) from the
risk, and (ii) he freely accepts the risk.
But the NCs in A1 fail to satisfy both of these conditions. So A1 imposes an unreasonable risk on the
NCs. Therefore, it is reckless. It is unjustified even though it satisfies
the DDE. We can now summarize Rodin’s
argument in the following way:[18]
1.
If
an action causes the foreseeable harming of NCs who have not surrendered their
relevant right, then it imposes an unreasonable risk on them.
2.
If
an action imposes an unreasonable risk on NCs, then it is reckless.
3.
If
an action is reckless, then it is unjustified.
4.
An
NC surrenders his relevant right only if both (i) he stands to benefit from the
risk, and (ii) he freely accepts it.
5.
It
is not the case that the NCs in A1 both (i) stand to benefit from the risk and
(ii) freely accept it.
6.
Therefore,
A1 is unjustified.
Although there is one objection to premise five worth
considering, I believe that it ultimately fails and this premise remains
plausible. I do believe, however, that
there is a more convincing objection to premise four, but I do not see it as a
serious setback to Rodin’s argument. As
I see it, the more serious problem with his argument lies with premise
one. I will discuss these objections in
the following section.
III. Some Objections.
One might
object to premise five by maintaining that the NCs in A1 do satisfy Rodin’s two
necessary conditions for the alienation of their relevant right: they do stand
to benefit from the risk and they freely accept it. These NCs stand to benefit from the risky
activity since, after all, they are subjected to these terrorist attacks as
well. And if they do not benefit
individually (e.g. they are killed in the attack), then their community will
certainly benefit. Finally, we might
also say that these NCs freely accept the risk of harm by allowing the
terrorists to maintain their residence in the community. Or perhaps they freely accept the risk in
virtue of their deciding to maintain residence in a known combat zone. If all of this is correct, then A1 satisfies
both of Rodin’s necessary conditions.
Premise five would be false.
But while it may be plausible to
argue that these NCs benefit from the risky activity, I am suspicious of the
claim that they freely accept the risk.
A lack of armed resistance to the terrorists does not entail free
acceptance of the risk of military attacks.
This would suggest that the NCs are morally obligated to resist the
terrorists. And while it might be
permissible for them to resists the terrorists, it seems implausible to suggest
that are morally obligated to do so. It
is more likely that their resistance would be supererogatory. Furthermore, to suggest that NCs have freely
accepted the risk of military attack simply in virtue of deciding to maintain
residence in a combat zone seems inconsistent with our intuitions on analogous
cases. For example, I know that there
are at least three gangs in the vicinity of my home. Suppose that I am shot during a drive-by
shooting. Now, it might be appropriate
to say that it would have been prudent of me to move out of the area, or to
limit my outdoor exposure. It might even
be correct to say that by not moving and going about my daily routine I
accepted the risk of being shot. But it
seems wrong to say that I freely
accepted this risk.[19] I think it is more likely that I freely
accepted the risk of getting shot only if I somehow supported or at least
condoned the gangs’ activities. And
while I may have done nothing to eliminate the gangs’ activities, I certainly
did not support or condone them.
Moreover, surely when we consider certain groups like infants and civic
leaders, the objection fails. There is
no sense in which infants, who have no choice but to remain, and civic leaders,
who have professional (and perhaps legal and moral) obligations to remain in
the area, have freely accepted the risk of military attack. If I am correct, then the objection to
premise five fails.
Although I
am inclined to agree with Rodin that an NC’s freely choosing to accept risk is
necessary for his losing his relevant right, I am not sure that it is necessary
that he stands to benefit from the risky activity. I suppose the rationale might go something
like the following. If we accept that an
NC must freely accept the risk to lose his relevant right, then we need only
accept the further claim that an NC freely accepts a risk only if he stands to
benefit from it. It would then follow
that an NC alienates his relevant right only if he stands to benefit from the
risk. But while it is unlikely that an NC would freely accept
a risk unless he stood to benefit from it, it is certainly possible. In other words, his freely accepting a risk
is probably a good indication that he stands to benefit from it, but it does
not logically follow from this.
Therefore, premise four is false.[20]
The most
serious problem with Rodin’s argument is with premise one, his core
premise. I agree that many standard
cases like A1 involve the foreseeable harming of NCs who maintain their
relevant right, and that these actions are reckless and unjustified if they
pose an unreasonable risk to NCs. But I
believe that Rodin is mistaken in suggesting that the foreseeable harming of
NCs who maintain their relevant right is ipso
facto unreasonable. I suspect that
this claim is based on the idea that foreseeable harm that inhibits one’s
relevant right entails the violation of that right. But while it might be the case that violating one’s relevant right is ipso facto unreasonable, I do not
believe that the foreseeable inhibition
of one’s right entails the violation of it. Let us return to A1. The pilot foresees that he will inhibit the
relevant right of the NCs, but it does not follow from this that he has
violated their right. Perhaps he has
violated their right only if he inhibits it unreasonably. But more is required for the unreasonable inhibition
of a right than simply inhibiting it.
Perhaps this right would be inhibited unreasonably if he intended to do
so, or if his action would result in far more NCs being killed than terrorists,
or if there was some way to eliminate the terrorist threat with less NC
casualties. In these cases, we might say
that an NC’s relevant right has been violated.
It has been violated because of the unreasonable risk of harm. But the unreasonableness of this harm is
adequately explained by the DDE.
One possible
reply from Rodin is that I have misinterpreted his premise one. Perhaps he is not claiming that the
foreseeable harming of an NC who maintains his relevant right is, by
definition, unreasonable. Rather, it
becomes unreasonable, a violation of his relevant right, if the proper standard
of care is not undertaken by those who inhibit the relevant right. He does suggest this in the following text:
If one is persuaded by these
interlinked lines of argument then one will feel that the standard of care
required of those engaged in military operations is high—higher than is
currently reflected in the laws of war.
One will be inclined to view many of the noncombatant casualties caused
in the course of military operations (including those of Western nations) to be
culpably reckless or negligent. One will
feel this despite the considerations adduced by the principle of double effect.[21]
So what makes some of the standard cases unreasonable and
reckless is that the proper standard of care has not been undertaken. This suggests that in standard cases there is
a level of care possible (even if it may be very high) such that the
foreseeable harm to NCs who maintain their relevant right would be reasonable.[22] But while I am more likely to agree with this
reasoning, I do not believe that it is Rodin’s.
He seems to think that there is no appropriate level of care in these
cases. In other words, the only
appropriate level of care would be to not harm the NCs. He suggests this below:
This analysis, of course, raises a
difficult question about how it can ever be justifiable to impose risk upon
those who have not through their actions made themselves specifically morally
vulnerable to it…my sense is that the answer has to do with two kinds of
consideration. The first is the kind of
free collective consent to beneficial but risky activities assumed by
communities [as discussed previously].
The second has to do with the much rarer set of cases in which there are
such overwhelming consequentialist considerations that we are inclined to
believe that it is justifiable to impose risks upon those who have done nothing
to deserve their imposition…[23]
So according to Rodin, while it might be justifiable to
impose risks upon NCs who have alienated their relevant right in virtue of
their freely accepting the risk, or upon those in “ticking time bomb” non-standard
cases, it is never justifiable to impose foreseeable risks on NCs in the
standard cases. I believe that this
supports my interpretation of premise one.
And if premise one is true, then one’s knowingly inhibiting another’s
right entails the violation of that right.
This seems implausible.
But let us suppose now that Rodin is
right about all of this. Suppose that A1
is unjustified for the reasons that Rodin suggests. What would we then say about his further claim
that the pilot in A1 (and the agents in other standard cases) is “morally
culpable to the same degree and for the same reasons that typical acts of
terrorism [those that intentionally harm NCs] are culpable?”[24] Let us consider a typical act of terrorism
(call it “A2”):
A2: An Al Qaida terrorist has set up a remotely controlled IED on the
side of the road. He allows a couple of
US and Iraqi military vehicles to pass before detonating the bomb as a school
bus full of children passes. He
intentionally kills the children. He
does this because he knows that many medical personnel will arrive at the scene
shortly thereafter. He intentionally
kills all of these NCs because he knows that this will lead to further destabilization
in the area, which will likely hamper Allied efforts.
Rodin contends that a typical act of terror like A2 “has the
significance it does in our moral thinking because the targets it attacks are
morally inappropriate.”[25] We find terrorism morally reprehensible
primarily because it attacks NCs who have not alienated their relevant
right. He explains that it is “this
feature of the core instances of terrorism which merit and explain the moral
reaction which most of us have toward them.”[26] So while A2 involves the intentional harming
of NCs, this does not help account for or influence our moral reaction to
it. The only morally relevant feature is
that it involves the foreseeable harming of NCs. It unreasonably harms them and is therefore
reckless. If all this is true, then an
act of unintentional “terrorism” (A1), which shares this same feature of
recklessness, merits the same moral reaction.
A1 is equally blameworthy to A2.
But while I agree that the reckless
nature of A2 accounts partly for our
moral reaction to it, it does not explain all of it. The terrorist merits additional blame for
intentionally killing the NCs. Even if
his intentionally killing them is superfluous to his action’s being
unjustified, surely it is relevant to his degree of moral culpability. Certainly, we think less of the terrorist
than we do of the pilot, even if both of their actions are reckless. This is not to say that the pilot is deserving
of no blame, that his lack of intention fully excuses him. If his action is reckless, then he may very
well be morally blameworthy to a high degree.
But not to a degree equal to that of the terrorist. In short, while it may be plausible to suggest
that intention is irrelevant to the moral status of an action, it is implausible
to claim that it is irrelevant to assessments of moral blame. Rodin seems committed to both of these
claims.
IV. Conclusion.
I have argued that Rodin’s argument
that standard cases like A1 are unjustified is unsound. For one, it seems unlikely that an NC
alienates his relevant right only if he stands to benefit from the risk,
although it is plausible that his free acceptance of the risk is
necessary. More importantly, although
many NCs harmed in the standard cases do maintain their relevant right, this
does not entail that an unreasonable risk has been imposed upon them. It does not entail that these actions are
reckless and unjustified. And although I
have not explicitly argued that a standard case’s satisfying the DDE is
sufficient justification for it, I have suggested as much. Finally, even if we accept that actions like
A1 are unjustified, this does not commit us to the further claim that they are
morally blameworthy to the same degree as typical acts of terrorism like
A2. This latter claim implies that
intention is morally irrelevant. This
seems very unlikely.
NOTES
[1] In Ethics 114 (July 2004): 752-771.
[2] Ibid., p. 755.
[3] Ibid., p. 767.
[4] Ibid.
[5] Ibid., p. 769. Rodin himself concedes, “But in reality, very little turns on the purely terminological question of the usage of the word ‘terrorism’. The important issue is whether one accepts the substantive argument put forward in this article: that the unintentional killing of some NCs in the course of military operations is morally culpable to the same degree and for the same reasons that typical acts of terrorism are culpable.” However, one might wonder if Rodin is more concerned with his definition of ‘terrorism’ than he lets on. After all, he seems eager to point out the irony in the United States’ fighting a war against terrorism using “terrorist” means. Nevertheless, I will focus my objections on Rodin’s substantive argument.
[6] The “standard cases” that Rodin has in mind are the attacks “against those targets within or adjacent to civilian populations which [are] almost certain to generate noncombatant casualties” (Ibid., p. 762). In particular, he refers to the tactical air strikes conducted by Western powers and their allies in Kosovo, Afghanistan, and Iraq. He argues that while many of these actions satisfy the DDE, they are nevertheless reckless, unjustified, and no better than traditional acts of terrorism.
[7] Ibid., p. 762. So a pilot’s targeting a military facility while foreseeing that it will likely harm some innocent bystanders is justified just in case (i) the harming of the innocent is neither the end of his action nor a means to his end, (ii) the good of his action outweighs the risk of harm to the innocent, and (iii) there is no way to reduce the risk of harm to the innocent while achieving his good.
[8] Ibid., p. 764.
[9] I will return to this point shortly.
[10] I have similar concerns about the supposed proportionality of this action. Although Rodin wants to construct the case in such a way as to satisfy proportionality, I am unconvinced that it does. Part of the motivation for the intuition that the motorist’s actions are unjustified might also come from our considering that the motorist is risking the lives of several children to save one sick person. This hardly sounds proportional.
[11] Rodin, p. 764.
[12] Ibid., p. 765.
[13] Ibid.
[14] Ibid., p. 766.
[15] Ibid.
[16] Ibid., pp. 766-7.
[17] Ibid., p. 767.
[18] This is my interpretation of Rodin’s argument. See Ibid., pp. 762-770.
[19] Perhaps I would have freely accepted the risk if the responsible gang leader had given prior announcement for the shooting. If this is true, then perhaps the same could be said in the standard military cases. I think it’s plausible to suggest that had the military warned all civilians and given them ample time to evacuate, then their staying in the area would constitute free acceptance of the risk. But I am still not sure about this.
[20] It might be the case that I misinterpreted Rodin’s premise four. Perhaps all he means to say is that an NC’s freely accepting a risk is a good indication that he stands to benefit from it. If this is true, then his premise four is more likely the following: An NC surrenders his relevant right only if he freely accepts the risk. Premise five could then be modified to maintain the validity of the argument: It is not the case that the NCs in A1 freely accept the risk. But while these modifications would make Rodin’s argument for plausible, I believe that there is a more substantial problem with premise one. I will discuss this problem next.
[21] Rodin, p. 767.
[22] If this is true, then Rodin’s premise one would be something like the following: If an action causes the foreseeable harming of NCs who have not alienated their relevant right without the proper standard of care, then it poses an unreasonable risk. For a similar view, see Michael Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars (New York: Basic, 1977), pp. 151-9. In addressing the shortcomings of the traditional DDE, Walzer writes, “But we have to worry…about all those unintended but foreseeable deaths, for their number can be large; and subject only to the proportionality rule—a weak constraint—double effect provides a blanket justification” (p. 153). He argues that what is also required is that “the foreseeable evil be reduced as far as possible” (p. 155). But it is important to note that Walzer’s and Rodin’s views are different in at least two respects. First, Walzer believes that intention is morally relevant to the justification of the action while Rodin does not. Second, Walzer’s addition allows that soldiers can be justified in the foreseen killing of NCs. Rodin’s view does not.
[23] Rodin, p. 769.
[24] Ibid.
[25] Ibid., p. 757.
[26] Ibid., p. 753.