Professional Obligation, Conscientious Objection, and the Military: A
Kantian Approach
Andrew Fiala, Ph.D.
Associate Professor of Philosophy
Department of Philosophy
California State University, Fresno
2380 E. Keats Ave. M/S MB 105
Fresno, CA 93740
(559) 278-2124
This paper considers the question of what military
“professionals” (not conscripts—but those who sign up of their own free will)
should do when they have a principled moral disagreement with the wars they are
asked to fight. I approach this topic as
a question of professional ethics.[1] A non-conscript military consists of
professional soldiers who are obligated by the standards and commitments of
their profession. In our system of
government, this profession is regulated by the principle of civilian control:
professional soldiers in a democracy have a duty to obey the orders of
democratically elected civilian leaders.
A useful principle in thinking about this issue is Kant’s idea that in a
republic, political professionals should “argue but obey.” The Kantian approach requires faith in the
institutions and procedures of deliberative democracy. Deliberative democracy is not perfect: but it
is less pernicious than the alternatives—either the blind and silent obedience
of authoritarianism or the radical disobedience of revolution. “Argue but obey” makes sense so long as one
has faith that the state is, in Kant’s sense, enlightened.
My focus here is disagreement about
the application of ad bellum
principles. I am not focusing on
questions of orders within a war that violate principles of jus in bello. It is fairly obvious that a soldier should
disobey an order to shoot infants, poison a water supply, or engage in
rape. But it is not so obvious what a
soldier should do when he disagrees with the ad bellum judgment about the overall justness of the cause and of
the war. The difficulty of this question
has to do with the general difficulty of making judgments about jus ad bellum. Such judgments are based upon imperfect
information. And they are fraught with
political complication, historical complexity, and uncertainty.
My thesis is that professional
soldiers should—for the most part—obey but argue. Their obedience should be based upon their
faith in republican structures of governance and in the closely allied
principle of civilian control of the military.
Indeed, it is this very democratic structure that allows them to argue
against mistaken decisions about jus ad
bellum. Their ability to argue
should be seen as justifying their faith in the potential for self-correction
in the democratic system. A soldier’s
professional duty requires obedience.
But in a democratic system that emphasizes civilian control of the
military, a soldier’s obedience is grounded in his faith in the moral
sensitivity of the procedures of deliberative democracy to the rights of
citizenship. It is this democratic
system, after all, that commands his allegiance.
The Paredes and Watada
Cases
This question is made concrete in
recent cases like those of Army Lieutenant Ehren Watada and Naval Petty Officer
Pablo Paredes—both of whom refused to serve in the Iraq War. Paredes refused to board his ship as it left
San Diego for the Persian Gulf in December of 2004. He claimed that a soldier has a duty to
disobey illegal orders—and he based this argument upon his understanding of
principles that were articulated in the war crimes tribunals at Nuremburg and
Tokyo. In the statement he read to the
court, Paredes explained himself as follows: “In all I read I came to an
overwhelming conclusion supported by countless examples that any soldier who
knowingly participates in an illegal war can find no haven in the fact that
they were following orders, in the eyes of international law.”[2] The basic idea here is that after Nuremburg
(and in the U.S. after My Lai), soldiers are presumed to have a moral
responsibility to disobey immoral orders.[3] And he extends this responsibility beyond jus in bello questions such that it
includes a soldier’s response to ad
bellum questions.
The difficulty of Paredes’ argument is
that the U.S. invasion of Iraq was not strictly analogous to the Nazi or
Japanese war crimes that provide the modern basis for this principle. Even Paredes admits this—saying explicitly
that he is NOT comparing American policies to German or Japanese atrocities. Nonetheless, Paredes grounds his
conscientious refusal in the basic principle guiding the tribunals in Nuremburg
and Tokyo. In Paredes’ words, this
principle is “that a service member must not participate in random
unprovoked illegitimate violence simply because he is ordered to.”[4]
Watada’s refusal to go to Iraq in
June of 2006 was similar to Paredes.
Watada also claimed that he did not want to participate in “war
crimes.” This way of putting the
disagreement is important. Watada and
Paredes have both argued that the U.S. invasion of Iraq was criminal and that
for a soldier to participate in an illegal war is a war crime. Both refused to engage in a war that they
claimed violated principles of the U.S. Constitution as well as principles of
international law. And they claim that
civil disobedience by soldiers is necessary as a response to this illegal
war. As Watada put it in an interview on
“Democracy Now!”: “We all have a duty as American citizens for civil
disobedience, and to do anything we can within the law to stop an illegal war.”[5] Watada’s claim contains a contradiction that
points to the heart of the problem: civil disobedience is—by definition—illegal and so it is not “within the
law.” Argument and protest are, of
course, within the law. And the Kantian
view maintains exactly what Watada says here: that one should have recourse to
legal means for combating bad policy.
But conscientious refusal by military professionals is not one of those
legal means.
Perhaps Watada simply misspoke in
making this off the cuff remark in his interview with Amy Goodman. But he points to a deeper problem here. If the war we are fighting is illegal, then the law that requires
obedience becomes illegitimate. And so
when soldiers (or anyone else for that matter) are confronted with the choice
of disobeying an unjust law or violating a criminal policy, the very idea of
what is “within the law” is in question.
The decision to disobey an apparently legal order indicates a profound
lack of faith in the legitimacy of the law.
And so once one has decided that a war is immoral or illegal, the answer
is obvious: there is no legal duty to fight in an illegal war and no moral duty
to fight in an immoral war.
Indeed, our obligations can shift
rapidly once we judge the cause to be wrong.
John Rawls puts this point quite strongly. According to Rawls, not only may a conscript
refuse to fight in a war that he judges to be unjust but also: “If the aims of
the conflict are sufficiently dubious and the likelihood of receiving
flagrantly unjust commands is sufficiently great, one may have a duty and not only a right to refuse”
(emphasis added).[6] Rawls continues to say that in this day and
age (he is writing in the midst of the Vietnam War), large and powerful states
are “so likely to be unjust that one is forced to conclude that in the
foreseeable future one must abjure military service altogether.” And he concludes that systematic
conscientious refusal would be pragmatically useful since it would make the
continuation of an unjust war “impossible.”
But how does one know that an entire
war is illegal or immoral? And how do we
know that we not only have a right to refuse but also a duty to refuse, as Rawls puts it?
There are no easy answers here.
There appears to be a sort of sliding scale here: the more we suspect
immorality the stronger our duty to resist.
The obvious model is the Nazi one: German soldiers should have refused
to carry out Nazi orders. But what about
wars that are not exactly Nazi wars?
Although I believe that the Iraq war was not justified, the difficulty
is that the case of Iraq is not as obviously unjust as Nazi aggression. The Iraq war had as one of its justifications
the humanitarian argument that aimed to end tyranny. The ad
bellum judgment with regard to Iraq is more complex than either critics or
defenders of the war often want to admit.
But how much certainty is needed
before a soldier jumps into the abyss of conscientious refusal? I use the word “abyss” here in the sense of
existentialists like Camus. Ultimately
we are on our own and each of us must decide for ourselves what we think is
right even to the point of rejecting our professional obligations and
allegiance to the state. We do have a
radical sort of autonomy to choose to be neither a victim nor an
executioner. Each man’s conscience is
his own. Even Huntington admits this:
“for the officer this comes down to a choice between his own conscience on the
one hand, and the good of the state, plus the professional virtue of obedience,
upon the other.”[7] Thus I must admit that I am compelled by the
sort of existential courage it took Paredes and Watada to make their decision.
But I am also troubled by the
implications of allowing soldiers the freedom to choose when to fight. I am frankly frightened of the idea that
soldiers should be able to subvert the principle of civilian control and take
matters into their own hands. Thus I
find myself profoundly ambivalent about these cases, even though I am, for the
most part, a pacifist and a critic of war.
The problem is that prior to that utopian time in which we dismantle our
armies, we need soldiers to obey the orders of civilian authorities; the
alternative is a military that could run amok.
Democratic peoples should not encourage military professionals to make
their own judgments about war. Rather,
we want those sorts of judgments to rest in the hands of elected officials like
the Congress and the President.
Paredes is right to advocate the
basic principle that a service member must not participate in “random
unprovoked illegitimate violence” simply because he is ordered to. But the difficulty is in applying this
principle to the concrete case. Is Iraq really
a case of “random unprovoked illegitimate violence”? While Watada and Paredes can mount persuasive arguments to
justify conscientious refusal based upon this sort of principle, these
arguments can be rebutted by equally persuasive arguments on the other
side. In other words, it is quite
difficult in this case to come to final conclusions about the application of
the principles of jus ad bellum. Some wars are obviously unjust and they
should be resisted. German officers
should have refused to obey Nazi orders.
But aside from this sort of case, things are much more complicated.
My reluctance to whole-heartedly
affirm Watada’s and Paredes’ refusals is further influenced by the fact that
these soldiers were volunteers who joined the service freely and who at one
time believed that their service was justifiable. These are not conscripts but professional
soldiers who signed up to defend the Constitution (please note, by the way,
that Rawls’ discussion is primarily about conscript armies). When soldiers volunteer, they willingly
oblige themselves to obedience. And this
obedience is grounded in the faith that the American political system is, for
the most part, just and worth defending.
When professional soldiers take the
step into civil disobedience they make a political claim about the illegitimacy
of this very political structure. These
soldiers lost faith in the deliberative democratic processes that provide
civilian control of military decisions.
In a system that cherishes civilian control, soldiers do have the
opportunity to rectify bad decisions about jus
ad bellum by working through the political process. It is important to note that this sort of
democratic remedy was not available to German or Japanese soldiers. In taking the step into disobedience, these
soldiers implicitly indicated (occasionally explicitly said) that they thought
the republican process had been corrupted to such an extent that there was no
redress for injustice save in breaking the law.
There may be times that professional soldiers should take this step—say when
the Nazi party rose to power in Germany.
But one must be clear about the moral and political significance of this
step—it is one that should be taken only when the republican system itself has
been shown to be essentially corrupted.
The Kantian Background
My approach draws on Kant’s idea that
professionals should “argue but obey” (as articulated in Kant’s essay “What is
Enlightenment?”). The principle of
“argue and obey” makes best sense in the context of an “enlightened” state,
i.e., a just “republican” state, or what we now call “deliberative democracy.”[8]
In this context, even though “political
professionals”—soldiers, diplomats, and even public school teachers—might
disagree with a policy, their professional duty is to remain obedient. The remedy for bad policy is found in the
political right to question and criticize that is the hallmark of the
“enlightened” state. An enlightened
state, in Kant’s terms, will allow extensive “freedom to make public use of one’s reason in all
matters,” including the freedom to criticize the government. But Kant recognizes that “private” reason—by
which Kant means the speech and activities of professional life—is different: a professional must obey. Kant directly addresses soldiers and
maintains that they must do what their “private” or professional obligations
require. But Kant also recognized that
soldiers should be free to engage in public debates about the merits of the
policies they were obeying. Kant’s
conclusion is: “argue as much as you like
about whatever you like, but obey.”
The important caveat is that this holds only as long as the state is
enlightened, i.e., so long as it actually allows the free exercise of public
reason as the remedy for bad policy.
This idea has much in common with an
argument made recently by David Estlund regarding a soldier’s duty to obey
orders if he has reason to believe that there are sufficient institutional
safeguards in place to ensure that wars are, for the most part, just. Estlund’s argues that “when the political and
institutional process producing the commands is duly looking after the question
whether the war is just, the soldier would be wrong to substitute his own
private verdict and thwart the state’s will.” [9] Estlund further argues that the soldier needs
to think hard and long about whether the state is actually interested in
fighting a just war. This requires deep
reflection into the question of whether the institutions of republican
political life are functioning and healthy.
Estlund seems to believe that the U.S. has mostly fought just wars: and
so the burden of proof rest on the proponent of disobedience. Paredes and Watada appear to make a different
assumption about American military power: one more influenced by critics such
as Noam Chomsky, Howard Zinn, and Chalmers Johnson.
This leads us toward some deep and
vexing question about whether there actually are just wars and whether the
American military has fought just wars.
I won’t discuss this here.[10] Rather, I want to focus on the question of
whether the constitutional system is legitimate and whether soldiers should
keep faith in the procedures of civilian control. The hope of scholars such as Doyle and Rawls
is that democracies tend to fight just wars.
But there is no guarantee here: democracies produce demagogues and
demagogues can use war to consolidate power.
Nonetheless, deliberative democracy and civilian control of the military
are the best set of procedural safeguards we have. To give up faith on these procedures is to
take a radical step into revolutionary politics.
Sometimes we must take the step into
revolution. Soldiers have no
professional obligation to obey in an unjust political system; and indeed,
citizens in an unjust political system should engage in civil disobedience and
even revolution to change the system.
This principle allows us to criticize the “professional” German soldier
for following Nazi orders (although one should note that Nazi soldiers were not
free from coercion). But we should note
that the basic problem behind the injustice of the German invasion of
Czechoslovakia was the corruptness of the authoritarian Nazi regime that
engaged in this war. In other words, the
question of a professional soldier’s obedience with regard to ad bellum questions points to a deeper
question about the constitutional order itself.
By disobeying the order to deploy Watada and Paredes were both
indicating that they had given up hope on the constitutional order they had
pledged to defend: they believed that the remedies of ordinary political life
were insufficient to ensure the justice of the decision. This step rests on judgments that go much
deeper than the ad bellum question of
whether the Iraq war was a just one; these judgments are about the legitimacy
and efficacy of republican government.
The Kantian approach reminds us that
one has a duty to obey as a professional but that as a citizen one has a duty
to work for a just social order. The implications of the Kantian idea extend to a variety of
professions, especially those professions that are linked to political life:
teaching, civil service, police, and the military. These “political professionals” are those who
work for the state and whose work helps to support the state. The analysis presented here might thus also
apply, for example, to the issue of whether diplomats could be forced to serve
in Iraq—as was suggested by the State Department in October of 2007; or whether
teachers should obey the policies of “No Child Left Behind.”
Political professionals
have a duty to obey legitimate civilian authorities and to conform to the
standards of their professional service.
But in an enlightened republican state, these professionals remain
citizens and as citizens they retain the privilege of arguing against the
state. When a soldier suspects that a
war is unjust his duty as a citizen is to exercise the prerogatives of
citizenship, while his duty as a soldier is to obey. There is substantial tension here. But this tension is productive of political
activity. If soldiers and their friends,
families, and neighbors took this tension seriously, it would help to ensure
that wars are fought justly because it would help to increase the political
effort that is made to change the war policy.
There is a
substantial amount of political work to be done
before a professional soldier resorts to conscientious objection and civil
disobedience. As in the ad bellum principle of “last resort,”
one cannot just leap into war or into disobedience: other less radical methods
must be used and used more then once before the radical last resort can be
employed. Disobedience, violence, and
war are extreme measures for extreme situations. To disobey is to express a profound loss of
faith in the legitimacy of government as a whole. Professional soliders—in the U.S. at
least—swear obedience to the principles of republican government, including the
ideal of civilian control. It is only
when a soldier fears that these principles themselves are in jeopardy that he
can disobey. But nota bene, no solider can be obligated to remain silent:
professional soldiers cannot be required to give up the privilege of
citizenship. If they were forced into
silent acquiescence, this would be a sign that the system was no longer worth
defending.
Moderate Republicanism and Civil Disobedience
The Kantian hope is that, in the long-run, democratic
deliberation will produce just outcomes.
This approach does not advocate radical revolution. Revolutions begin with conscientious
objection and civil disobedience. [11] Kant’s ideal of “argue but obey” is not
revolutionary. Rather, it rests within
the mainstream of republican politics and is a sort of pragmatic compromise
between the rival extremes of authoritarian politics and radical revolution. The following chart attempts to map the
terrain here.
Radical/Revolutionary |
Republican/Democratic |
Authoritarian/Totalitarian |
Argue
and Disobey |
Argue
but Obey |
Obey
without Argument |
There are good reasons to stick to the middle path. Totalitarianism is an obvious evil. And we should also fear the anarchy that
would be introduced by a radical revolution in which military professionals
took matters into their own hands. There
is continuum from conscientious refusal to the military coup. It is dangerous to allow military professionals
to decide for themselves about when and who to kill.
Now some situations do call for conscientious refusal and
even revolution. But this is primarily
when there is an absence of republican political remedies for injustice. In general, the republican ideal is the
moderate position which allows for critique and progress while also ensuring
stability. Revolutionary activity aims
at progress but brings about instability.
Thus there are good pragmatic reasons to avoid the radical step into
revolution—especially so long as we have faith in the responsiveness of
republican institutions. A gradual or
moderate approach to reforming the institutions of social and political life is
needed. This is especially true if the
basic structure of society is grounded in just constitutional principles that
are not in need of radical change.
Hope that the system will respond to critique is a closely
tied to this gradualist approach. For
Kant, hope for progress within the system is one of the things that causes the
system to make progress.[12] The hopeful idealism of the “argue but obey”
approach gives us a further practical incentive to make sure that our
institutions are just. If obedience to
the institutions of professional life—including the military—is morally
required, then citizens should aim to ensure that these institutions are as
just as possible. In the end, this
approach is grounded in Kant’s commitment to the Enlightenment’s
basic faith in the rationality of human nature and our potential for melioristic
improvement (not perfection but progress).
Kant believes that free public discourse will ultimately lead us toward
truth and goodness.[13] And for Kant, this process is
“self-developing” and “self-fertilizing.”[14] Faith that republican institutions are
reasonable helps to make them so.
Conscientious
objection and civil disobedience are thus only
of use when one has given up hope in the power of deliberative democracy to
create just outcomes and to correct injustices.
But one must bear in mind that the hope discussed here is a long-run faith. Justice is about the overall trajectory of
the ship of state. As long as one
remains hopeful that the overall course is just, it is not justified for
political professionals to turn to conscientious objection and civil
disobedience.
Conclusion
Professional life does not require blind and silent obedience. In a democracy, professionals always retain the rights of citizenship. In the U.S. even soldiers can vote for Congress and for the President. Unlike other professionals, however, military professionals are exposed to grave moral and physical risks: their professional duties ask them to kill and to be killed. One might think that this means that a military professional should be free to consult his or her own conscience. But the obligations of political professionals such as the military are special. A doctor in private practice may refuse to perform abortions without any threat to the political order. But we do not want soldiers to make their own decisions about war, since such decisions threaten the stability of the political order. In the same way, we do not want diplomats to make their own decisions about diplomacy or teachers to make their own decisions about what to teach.[15]
An important
principle in democracy is “civilian control” of the military. We want soldiers to obey the legitimate
policies of the Department of Defense, the Congress, and the
Commander-in-Chief. If soldiers disagree
with these policies, they have recourse to the “public” use of their reason:
they can argue and protest. But they
must also obey.
One important objection to the view presented here is that it places too much faith in our democracy. Throughout the later half of the 20th Century, critics such as Herbert Marcuse argued that our “one-dimensional” society tends toward conformity and the path of least resistance. Such critics worry that passive acquiescence to the military-industrial complex is one small step away from authoritarianism. This sort of criticism goes back to Marxist critiques of the Kantian faith in republican principles. Kant’s solution can appear to be rationalization for a timid sort of bourgeois complacency that is simply afraid of revolution.
In response I argue that a revolution against an authoritarian regime is not ruled out by this approach. One certainly wishes that German soldiers would have staged a revolution against Nazism. But there are good reasons to restrict the revolutionary response only to times when republican principles have been subverted. Soldiers such as Paredes and Watada have argued that recent history including the U.S. invasion of Iraq represents such a crisis. Empirical and historical evidence is needed to make such a judgment. Although I agree that the invasion of Iraq was not justified, there is a qualitative difference between this invasion and the German invasion of Czechoslovakia and a qualitative difference between the American constitutional system under George W. Bush and the Nazi regime under Adolph Hitler.
We should not encourage soldiers and other political professionals to disobey since this would mean that they would take the law into their own hands. Civilian control of the military is essential in a democracy. Rather than disobedience, then, the solution is more and better deliberative democracy: private (i.e., professional) obedience for political professionals and military personnel; but more and better public argument. There is no panacea here. Deliberative democracy is not perfect—but it is less bad than the other alternatives: authoritarian politics or the anarchy of revolution.
Bibliography
Bedau, Hugo. “On Civil Disobedience” The Journal of Philosophy 58: 21 (1961).
Benhabib, Seyla. “Toward a Deliberative Model of Democratic Legitimacy,” in Seyla Benhabib, ed. Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1996.
Brandt, Richard. “Utilitarianism and the Rules of War” in Larry May, et al., eds., The Morality of War. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall, 2006.
Cohen,
Carl. “Conscientious Objection” Ethics
78:4 (1968).
Cohen, Joshua. “Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy” in Robert E. Goodin and Philip Pettit, eds., Contemporary Political Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing, 2006.
Estlund, David. “On Following Orders in an Unjust War.” The Journal of Political Philosophy 15: 2 (2007).
Fiala, Andrew. The Philosopher’s Voice: Philosophy, Politics, and Language in the Nineteenth Century. Albany: SUNY Press, 2002.
Fiala, Andrew. The Just War Myth. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 2008.
Glover, Jonathan. Causing Death and Saving Lives. New York: Penguin, 1977.
Glover, Jonathan. Humanity: A Moral History of the 20th Century. New Haven: Yale University Press, 2000.
Gutmann, Amy and Dennis Thompson. Why Deliberative Democracy? Princeton University Press, 2004.
Huntington, Samuel P. The Soldier and the State. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1957. Accessed in Malham M. Wakin, ed., War, Morality, and the Military Profession. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1981.
Johnson, James Turner. Just War Tradition and the Restraint of War. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1981.
Kant, Immanuel. Kant: Political Writings. Cambridge University Press, 1991.
May, Larry “Superior Orders, Duress, and Moral Perception” in Larry May, et al., eds., The Morality of War. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall, 2006.
McCloskey, H.J. “Conscientious Disobedience to the Law” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 40: 4 (1980).
Rawls, John. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971.
Walzer, Michael. Just and Unjust Wars. New York: Basic Books, 1977.
Wasserstrom, Richard. “Disobeying the Law” The Journal of Philosophy 58: 21 (1961).
Zinn, Howard. Disobedience and Democracy. New York: Random House, 1968.
NOTES
[1] This approach goes back, at least, to Samuel P. Huntington’s The Soldier and the State (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1957).
[2] Quoted on Democracy Now! May 13, 2005: http://www.democracynow.org/2005/5/13/war_resister_pablo_paredes_wins_surprise.
[3] For discussion see Larry May, “Superior Orders Duress, and Moral Perception in Larry May, Eric Rovie, and Steve Viner, The Morality of War (Pearson/Prentice Hall, 2006).
[4] Democracy Now! interview op cit..
[5] Democracy Now! June 8, 2006. (http://www.democracynow.org/2006/6/8/army_lieutenant_becomes_first_commissioned_officer). Also see an article in The Nation, “Lieutenant Watada’s War against the War” (June 26, 2006-- http://www.thenation.com/doc/20060626/brecherwebvideo)
[6] John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), 381.
[7] Huntington, The Soldier and the State, in Malham M. Wakin, War, Morality, and the Military Profession (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1981), p. 44.
[8] Kant’s essay, “What is Enlightenment?” can be found in Kant: Political Writings (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991). For discussion of deliberative democracy see: Joshua Cohen, “Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy” in Robert E. Goodin and Philip Pettit, eds., Contemporary Political Philosophy, 2nd Edition (Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing, 2006) or Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, Why Deliberative Democracy? (Princeton University Press, 2004).
[9] David Estlund, “On Following Orders in an Unjust War” The Journal of Political Philosophy 15: 2 (2007), 213.
[10] I do discuss this in some detail in Fiala, The Just War Myth (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 2008).
[11] For further discussion of the connection between civil disobedience and revolution see Richard Wasserstrom, “Disobeying the Law” The Journal of Philosophy 58: 21 (1961).
[12] I discuss this in detail in Fiala, The Philosopher’s Voice (SUNY, 2001).
[13] “Truth and goodness do not fail to communicate
themselves far and wide once they have become public, thanks to their natural
affinity with the moral predisposition of rational beings generally” [Kant, Religion
within the Limits of Reason Alone
(1793; Greene translation, Harper Torchbook, 1960), 113].
[14] Ibid.
[15] Estlund reminds us, in another example, that we expect jailers to obey the courts and juries who convict criminals; and that they shouldn’t employ their own individual judgment about what a criminal deserves.