Responsibility Towards Wounded Civilians
Midn 2C Jarrod Larson
Evan
Wright is a contributing editor for Rolling
Stone magazine. During the buildup to the invasion of
During an assault on an Iraqi airfield (while the book is not clear on the exact amount of resistance they receive, it is minimal) the Marines get word of a change in the Rules of Engagement (ROE) to include pretty much anything that moves. The Marines engage a group of Iraqis intermixed with camels in front of some nearby huts. After taking the airfield the Marines are approached by two Bedouin women dragging what turns out to be one of the women’s twelve-year-old son, who had been wounded during the attack. He is examined by the Navy corpsman attached to the unit, who determines, not only that he will die without immediate medical attention, but also that he was shot with four 5.56mm rounds, meaning he was shot by Marines. During this time an interpreter with the unit relays the grandmother's story of the shooting to the platoon commander. She explains that during the assault the family's camels were startled by the Humvees and her grandsons ran out after the camels, only to be gunned down by Marines. The brother is later brought in with a leg wound.[1]
The
platoon commander and battalion surgeon decide to request a medevac for the boy
from the battalion commander. Their repeated requests are repeatedly denied.
The battalion surgeon, a
This
situation raises an ethical dilemma that many soldiers in combat are likely to
face. The boy in this incident was wounded by fire from US Marines. In this
case it happened to be the indiscrete fire from a Squad Automatic Weapon, yet
it was allowable in accordance with the updated Rules of Engagement. Regardless
of how he was wounded, what the intentions were, or what was stated in the ROE,
the boy was wounded by US soldiers. The corpsman and several of the Marines
felt that it was their duty to seek out medical attention for the boy, even
though a medevac was repeatedly denied by the battalion commander. Here they
reached the dilemma of whether to obey their commander who twice refused a
medevac, or take matters into their own hands in order to save the boy's life.
I will argue that the Marines had a moral duty to see that the boy got the
medical attention he needed. The
The doctrine of Utilitarianism states that whatever decision results in the greatest amount of happiness is the right decision to make, and we therefore have a moral duty to make that decision.[4] It is fairly easy to see that the greatest happiness (in this case the greatest happiness results from the least amount of pain) will be achieved by providing medical attention to a wounded civilian. While the soldiers in the unit may have to endure hardships to ensure a civilian receives adequate medical attention, this is far outweighed by the opportunity to save that civilian's life. By evoking the Greatest Happiness Principle we can see that the greatest amount good for the greatest amount of people[5] will be achieved by seeking medical attention for civilians wounded by our own forces. Utilizing Utilitarianism we can see that it is our moral duty to provide medical attention to these wounded civilians, such as the boy in the opening story.
German philosopher Immanuel Kant stated that what is good is good because of its will and that an act is determined to be right based upon good intentions.[6] The intent to give aid to wounded civilians is obviously good, even more so when they were wounded by our own troops. By Kantian ideals this means that providing medical aid to said civilians is the morally right decision. Kant goes even further, stating that consequences do not factor in determining the moral worth of an action.[7] This means that the consequences of providing medical attention are not important. If the platoon commander or battalion surgeon were relieved for disregarding their superior's order, or if the Marines invasion was slowed down by seeking medical aid for the boy, it would not have mattered because the Marines were doing the right thing.
Natural Law theory states that even without set laws rational creatures will have a natural inclination to do what is right.[8] Soldiers, just like all other humans, are rational creatures and one can easily see that any person's natural inclination would be to assist wounded civilians. If they were wounded by our own side we should feel an even greater urge to help them. This is because giving them medical aid is the right thing to do, and as humans our conscious tells us that it is our moral duty to give them aid. One of the four inclinations of Natural Law is self-preservation, which instills a moral obligation to promote and sustain our own health and life[9]. This can be expanded to include a duty to sustain the lives of others, further influencing the need to provide civilians whom we wound the medical attention they need.
One
of the main tenants of the doctrine of the Conduct of War is that combatants
must place the safety of civilian non-combatants over their own, as soldiers
have a duty to preserve civilian lives even at the risk of their own.[10]
In the
On the flip side Utilitarianism can also be used to argue against providing medical aid to civilians wounded by our own forces. By stopping to provide medical attention to civilians which we have wounded we are essentially taking that unit, platoon, or squad out of the fight. This may expose us to a greater risk from the enemy and result in greater casualties to our troops. It may also stop us from aiding other civilians who may be in danger. In the long run, which Utilitarianism insists we consider, we may actually be doing a greater good for a greater number of people by not assisting wounded civilians, even though we may be responsible for their injuries. Additionally, by providing medical aid to civilians who we wound we could set a dangerous precedent. We may find ourselves constantly giving medical attention to wounded civilians, many of which may not have been wounded by our troops at all, but may take advantage of our situation. This will neutralize whatever that unit's primary mission was. In the end our soldiers are there to fight and beat the enemy, not to act as a personal ambulance service for the civilian population.
The best argument against providing medical aid to these wounded civilians comes from the constitutional paradigm. In the hierarchy of loyalties the mission is second from the top, beneath only the Constitution.[11] Civilians are not on the list but we can assume that they would be placed near the bottom. As mentioned earlier, aiding wounded civilians could seriously endanger the mission, regardless of whether they were wounded by US troops. Being how a soldier's ultimate duty is to the hierarchy of loyalties it may not be essential to provide medical assistance to civilians whom we have wounded.
Based on the evidence from varying forms of ethical reasoning there is significantly more support for providing aid to the civilians who our own soldiers have wounded. Not only do we have a duty to do what is right but also to minimize hardship on the civilian population as a result of our actions. As fighting men in our military we have a duty to provide for the protection of civilians. When we falter in our guarantee to ensure their protection by injuring them on the battlefield we take on a responsibility to do all we can to save their life. This includes ensuring that they receive the utmost medical attention based on their wounds.
While
there may be exceptions to the times in which we can provide medical aid to
civilians brought down by our bullets, as a general rule I feel that we have a
duty to provide as much aid as possible to civilians who are wounded by our
military. As a dominant world power, and especially as Americans, we have an
obligation to take the moral high ground in wartime. Providing appropriate medical attention to
civilians whom we have wounded is this high ground.
NOTES
[1] Evan
Wright. Generation Kill (
[2] Wright
[3] Wright
[4] John
Stuart Mill. "Utilitarianism," in Ethics and the Military Profession,
ed Dr. George R. Lucas Jr. and Captain W. Rick Rubel (
[5] Mill
[6] Immanuel
Kant. "Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals," in Ethics and the
Military Profession, ed Dr. George R. Lucas Jr. and Captain W. Rick Rubel (
[7] Kant
[8]
[9] Dr. C.
E. Harris. "The Ethics of Natural Law," in Ethics and the Military Profession,
ed Dr. George R. Lucas Jr. and Captain W. Rick Rubel (
[10] Dr.
George Lucas. "The Moral Code of the Warrior," in Ethics and the
Military Profession, ed Dr. George R. Lucas Jr. and Captain W. Rick Rubel (
[11] Colonel
Paul E. Roush. "Constitutional Ethics," in Ethics and the Military
Profession, ed Dr. George R. Lucas Jr. and Captain W. Rick Rubel (