"Military Ethics and
Virtues: The Attitudes Required for a Cross-Cultural/Inter-Religious
Dialogue"
Prof.
Michel Dion
Faculty
of Business Administration
Université de Sherbrooke
2500, boul. Université
J1K
2R1
Tel:
1-819-821-8000, ext. 62913
E-mail: Michel.Dion@USherbrooke.ca
Introduction
According to Aristotle, in all
nations which are able to gratify their ambition, military power is held in
esteem. He added that some nations have laws that stimulate "warlike
virtues"[1].
Military reflect the main values of their society, whether it is freedom,
equality, tolerance, respect for each other. It can hardly happen that military
will contradict the basic social values that define the essence of their
societal culture. But it could be the case. For instance, there could be a
society in which equality between men and women implies that there must be
neither discrimination, nor harassment against women, on one hand, and on the
other hand, male military who practice discrimination or harassment against
their female comrades. In other situations, questionable practices that are socially
tolerated or justified (such as torture, intimidation in the workplace) could
also be observed in the military services, as if military then acted as “people
in the street” (the “citizen-soldier”: the responsibility of the soldier as a
citizen; military are collectively guilty of the “crime of an unjust war”).
Military can also reflect the main values and attitudes that are shared in the
sub-continental area (for instance, the primacy of individual freedom in North
America, or the “saving face issue” in
I- Military Virtues
Military virtues are rooted in
military traditions and customs that have been developed throughout the history
of military services in a given country. They reflect the way virtues are
acquired according to Aristotle (384-322 B.C.). Aristotle said that virtue
acquisition implies three stages: (1) we undertake virtuous actions because of
the expected pleasure (reward) or pain (punishment) (the priority of rules);
(2) we adopt role models: virtuous people give the "example" (the
priority of role models); (3) we develop a habit of virtuous actions: "we
become just by doing just acts" (the priority of practicing virtue)[2].
It is interesting to notice how
Plato was defining the “cardinal virtues” as being rooted in our basic nature:
“Now goods
are of two kinds, human and divine; and the human goods are dependent on the
divine; and he who receives the greater acquires also the less, or else he is
bereft of both. The lesser goods are those of which health ranks first, beauty
second; the third is strength, in running and all other bodily exercises; and
the fourth is wealth (…) And wisdom, in turn, has first place among the goods
that are divine, and rational temperance of soul comes second; from these two,
when united with courage, there issues justice as the third; and the fourth is
courage. Now all these are by nature ranked before the human goods, and verily
the law-giver also must so rank them”[3].
(a) Traditional Military Virtues
(1) LOYALTY implies discipline (and thus self-control) and obedience
to orders: it does imply a notion of “partnership” (and thus a team spirit
and teamwork, and thus social cohesion within the troops) between superiors and
subordinates, particularly in mission fulfillment. Such partnership among
military officers and soldiers reflects a value of cooperation. In that
context, the scope and meaning of loyalty is not self-evident. Are soldiers
loyal to their superiors (moral obligation towards the superiors)? To the
troops (moral obligation towards the comrades as fellow soldiers)? To the
Commander-in-Chief (moral obligation towards the Commander-in-Chief)? To the
Army (moral obligation towards the Army itself)? To the country (moral
obligation towards the country)? Other levels of moral obligation are much less
self-evident: To the Minister of Defence? To the Prime Minister? To the
Constitution of their country? These are the theoretical levels of
accountability we have to discern in any ethical decision-making process
related to military services.
And what does it mean to be loyal in
each of these cases? Does it imply a blind (unreflective) obedience to
orders? As said Kaurin (1999), loyalty implies to use our rational
reflection and to consider our own feelings and moral values to analyze the
orders of our superiors. Loyalty is basically required to have an efficient
functioning of the military services[4].
Groll-Ya’ari (1994) said that there is an “unprecedented burden of
responsibility” implying that military personnel have been court-martialed and
punished for obeying the wrong order (checking every aspect of superiors’
orders: the responsibility for obeying unlawful or illicit (immoral) orders).
It means that soldiers can judge their superiors’ orders and even override such
orders in given critical situations"[5].
On the other hand, disobeying licit (moral) orders can open the door to
punishment for insubordination. Soldiers must then examine the licit (moral)
nature of orders they have to execute, and the risk to be punished for
insubordination (the level of doubt about the moral nature of orders). This is
what we could call the "enlightening process of obedience": moral
questioning is putting light on the effects of executing our superiors' orders.
And such a moral questioning must never be a process that reduces the trust relationships
between superiors and subordinates. Otherwise, the social cohesion within the
troops should be deeply harmed; basically, the military environment requires
obedience to superiors' orders. Indeed, the moral questioning of soldiers
should be seen as a way to reinforce hierarchical relationships based on mutual
trust. We must admit that it will require a high level of maturity from
superiors as well as subordinates. Obeying to orders does not mean that
soldiers cannot know the morality of committing atrocities, said Toner (2006).
A minimum moral knowledge is expected from every military. This moral knowledge
can vary from culture to culture, but it should never exclude the universal
norms of ethical behaviour that are transmitted through the various sources of
natural law. There is an “a priori” principle that military orders are legal
and should then be executed. However, realities could be different, so that we
should not obey the order if we believe that the “impartial spectator” (the
reasonable person using his/her common sense and referring to given ethical
values) would consider the order as being immoral;
(2) moral and physical COURAGE: courage implies risk, and then
the awareness of potential dangers. If there is no risk, we cannot claim that
our action was courageous. But does courage imply to overcome given fears? Are
we courageous if we do not feel any kind of fear in face of objective risks?
Indeed, risk is connected either to potential dangers (the perception of known
dangers or the apprehension of unknown dangers), or to the lack of knowledge
about the risky situation (a given action could be risky because we have few
information about it, so that we are not sure that our action is the optimal
decision, considering the situation). Insofar as risk is related to dangers
and/or a lack of knowledge about a given situation, fear could arise in our
state of mind: either a fear closely linked to the arising of the danger, or a
fear not to take the right decision. It is quite clear for physical courage
(physical integrity, suffering and death). As said Rollo May (1950), fear has a
specific object. "In fear, we are aware of ourselves as well as of the
object, and we can orient ourselves spatially with reference to the thing
feared (…) In fear, your attention is narrowed from the object because it
occupies a particular point spatially"[6].
Courage requires fear, because risks imply fears. It is not a risk if we do not
fear to see it actualized. In that sense, courage is the state of mind that
makes us possible to overcome our fears, not to get rid of them
(fear-overcoming). According to Aristotle, courage is particular displayed in
face of "objects of fear". Those who are not troubled in face of
terrors will behave rightly as courageous beings "in a fuller sense"
than those who rightly behave in situations that inspire confidence. It does
not mean that courage implies fearlessness, but rather that the most courageous
beings are not troubled when they are facing terrors. In that case, the most
courageous beings will suffer pain "unwillingly" but endure them
because it is noble to do so, said Aristotle. The highest level of courage is
then linked to a sense of nobility, or honour[7].
According to Aristotle, human beings who suffer pain with angry and take
pleasure in revenge are not courageous people, since the motive of their
confidence is not honour. They are ruled over by their emotions[8].
Their emotion "cooperates with them". Cooperation between emotion and
the whole personality of brave people could consist in the fact that fear makes
prudence possible. It is quite important when one faces unforeseen dangers
since in that case the individual cannot prepare himself/herself throughout
calculation and reference to principles of action.
Now, what kind of risk is involved in
moral courage? The risk that is assumed is connected to the possibility to
choose the morally wrong alternative of action, particularly when the situation
is morally ambiguous. Moral courage is based on a strong belief that our action
is morally grounded and on the willingness to face the adverse effects that
such action will have on our self-interest (social status, friendship, etc.).
Now, can courage involve fearlessness? Such strange assertion could be made[9].
However, it is very difficult to find out philosophical and psychological
grounds for such a "revolutionary notion of courage". Is courage as
fearlessness possible? Courage as fearlessness could be identified in a
Buddhist framework, since the belief in reincarnation does insist on the necessity
to get rid of any fear, particularly the fear to die. However, Buddha
proclaimed the absolute primacy of non-violence. He said that conquering our
self is better than the conquest of other people (Dhammapada, 104-105).
According to Buddha, he who kills other beings (those beings were searching for
their own happiness), will never find happiness after his death (Dhammapada,
131). In that context, courage as fearlessness is not courage as such, because
there is no independent self that could be qualified as being
"courageous".
(3) INTEGRITY, RESPECT, and HONOUR: honour seems to be closely linked
to acts of courage as well as a sense of honesty or integrity. But the sense of
integrity is itself a condition for trust to be developed. Trust is inspired by
integrity and respect. We cannot trust dishonest people: the lack of trust is
due to the discontinuity between our own notion of honesty and others'
behaviour. Integrity is required to be both a person of honour and a reliable
individual. A lack of integrity from people we know makes us reducing our trust
in them. In the same way, trust is inspired by the respect we receive from
others. If we are not respected by our superiors, they seem to consider
ourselves not as persons or subjects. Then how could we trust them?
(4) SERVICE TO THE COUNTRY: this is a moral duty towards collective
welfare and more particularly to the country (defending public/national
interest and supporting national policies, protecting the State). However,
military are apolitical. Service to the country implies an attitude of
self-sacrifice. According to Snider, Nagl and Pfaff (2000), the duty of
military officers is to serve society, that is, "to provide that which
they cannot provide for themselves - security". Snider et al (200) believed
that there is a moral obligation between military officers and the society they
serve. Military officers are then conceived as "agents of society[10].
(b) Military Leadership
Leaders can make possible for their
followers (subordinates) to exploit their potentialities (transformational
leadership)[11].
Ethical leaders are those leaders who can mould the ethics of their
organization. Toner (2006) said that “moral failures by the troops are at heart
leadership failures”[12].
According to Groll-Ya’ari (1994), military leaders must always be ready to
lead, and thus:
(a) leading by example (through deeds and words), that is, performing our
duties with excellence: as said
Toner (1998), "the commander must be a "model of excellence"[13].
Excellence would mean that military leaders are able to harmonize their
spiritual values, physical needs (and integrity) and (mental) self-control,
said Snider et al (2000). Ethical organizations have ethical leaders. Ethical
leadership is a condition to develop an ethical culture within a given
organization. There are other conditions that are required to ensure that a
given organization will have an "ethical substance";
(b) providing competence in order to ensure reliability of military forces:
ensuring that combat operations are led with the optimal level of skill, expertise and knowledge,
(c) carrying out military missions
successfully (mission fulfilment):
military officers are those who succeed in military missions and whose actions
are considered as the right ones (such actions indeed contributed to the
success of military missions). In given situations, particular conducts (such
as intimidation, harassment) can reduce, if not destroy, the combat
effectiveness and even cause the death of many comrades, said Toner (2006).
Toner (2006) rightly suggested that we could adopt: (i) a “microscopic/pragmatic
perspective” (deriving ethics from the requirements of military operations:
developing the sense of ethics out of military purposes, that is, the ends
justify the means (Machiavelli: for instance, deliberately killing innocents,
destructing properties). In that case, military necessity is easily to define
and declare. Moral action is seen as actually increasing military
effectiveness, or (ii) a “macroscopic perspective” (applying an
overarching sense of ethics to military situations): mission fulfillment should
never be the ultimate consideration in military ethics, said Toner (2006),
because some victorious military operations could be linked to unjust wars and
conflicts. Military success in given missions, military purposes and military
necessity should never be considered as ultimate ethical criteria. The
macroscopic perspective refers to virtues as “practices of thinking wisely and
acting justly”, said Toner (2006), that is, to the virtue of wisdom and that of
justice;
(d) using human and material
resources with the highest effectiveness
and a minimum rate of losses (minimizing collateral damages): here, we
could identify two different notions of evil: (i) the evil coming from military
intervention; (ii) the evil following from the non-intervention. Then, we
should compare both notions of evil and see to what extent damages are more
important in the case of the intervention or in the case of the
non-intervention. To resolve the problem, we must have a "hierarchy of
damages" (and then a utilitarian moral calculus could become
possible). However, we must understand that such hierarchy is basically
qualitative, so that it will not be self-evident if some damages (for instance,
to the environment) should be equivalent to other damages (for instance,
civilians' death), or not. The hierarchy of damages (or pains) implicitly
refers to a hierarchy of pleasures. A utilitarian approach of ethical issues
favours the highest happiness (more pleasures than pains) for the greatest
number of people who are affected by the decision or action[14].
II- Cross-cultural and Inter-Religious Dialogue on
Ethical Issues in the Military Services
A multicultural society implies a
plurality of cultures. Most of the time, such cultures do not share the same
definition and scope of ethics. It is particularly true when we consider
religions as such. Is it possible to get a common meaning and scope for ethics
and ethical behaviour? There is no need to discuss cultural and religious
conditionings of basic human rights when such rights are violated. For
instance, we must not spend time to discuss about the so-called cultural and
religious conditionings of an "ethical cleansing or genocide" (like
in Serbia/Croatia/Bosnia/Kosovo conflict; the East Timor conflict; the
World religions could exert pressure
on political leaders in order to facilitate a cross-cultural/inter-religious
dialogue on the global scene and to reduce the potential conflicts that could
give birth to wars.
"On this
level the world religions, drawing directly upon the sources for peace in their
traditions, can begin to challenge world leaders to make the practical
adjustments and, indeed, political concessions necessary to diminish the
horrifying potential for nuclear war that hangs over all of us like the sword
of Damacles by a precariously frayed thread"[15].
Ethical Attitudes Required for a
Cross-Cultural/Inter-Religious Dialogue
(1) I know that I don’t know: Miller (2004) rightly said that
the Socratic inquiry implies the following stages: (i) to examine our
intuitions, (ii) to probe the reasons that we give to justify those responses;
(iii) to test such justifications against other intuitions until we get more
general principles that we can accept. In that sense, the Socratic attitude
implies to ask questions rather than looking at answers, so that through the
act of talking about justice and courage, we are becoming someone who is more
just and courageous, said Wortel and Schoenmakers (2006)[16].
As said Toner (1998), "the fact that we do not know everything does not
mean that we do not know some things". Toner (1998) said that people
usually understand what fairness is all about. It implies a pre-philosophical
understanding of the meaning of fairness, that is, the scope of fair attitudes
and behaviours. We are always searching for truth. Human being is a being who
is continuously searching for truth, throughout the main components of human
existence (inner life/self; interpersonal life/others; natural life/Nature;
spiritual life/God, social life/Society)[17].
Throughout this "quest for truth", values could be considered as
social constructs[18].
They are moulded by the culture and society we live in. They are partially
inherited from our family, adapted to some loci of socialization (school,
friends, workplace) including some opportunities of benevolent involvement
(community involvement, membership in a political party, adherence to a given
religion or spirituality). When we "feel" what fairness is all about,
it means that: (a) we have experienced the past fair and unfair behaviours and
attitudes from others (and ourselves); (b) we have constructed a notion of
fairness out of various meanings we received from various external conditioning
factors and we have internalized this notion of fairness.;
(2) My perception of those behaviours that are universally considered as
"good/bad, right/wrong": Toner (1998) said that human beings
have a natural, innate knowledge of goodness and evil. How can we explain
horrors and atrocities if human beings have such an innate knowledge? How could
we justify the existence of such knowledge within human nature? The fact that
all cultures, countries and eras recognized some core right/wrong behaviours
(killing, stealing, for instance) could be interpreted as the effect of the
historical development of civilizations rather than the reflection of the human
“essence”. If we accept that there is no such innate knowledge of right/wrong,
then we are asserting that such knowledge is purely cultural, so that there is
a possibility that future civilizations get rid of it. So, either the knowledge
of right/wrong is natural, and then we cannot explain the arising of evil in
human existence, or it is cultural (and then it could take multiple forms and
could potentially disappear as it is a social construct). We could resolve the
paradox in saying that human beings have the intuition of what is universally
considered as right/wrong. Such innate intuition is not knowledge of goodness
and evil, but a pre-philosophical understanding of them. Cultures and
civilizations can mould the way individuals will interpret their own
pre-philosophical understanding of goodness and evil. In military operations,
the perception of right/wrong could give birth to an ethical dilemma for soldiers: (1) they have learned (in their
family life and from legal constraints) that killing a human being is morally
wrong; (2) military operations could impose to kill some people in order to
ensure public security. It is already self-evident that pacifists (such as
Quakers and Mennonites) will refuse to be soldiers. But for those who believe
in international peace but also on the necessity of military operations in
given situations, the (personal) ethical dilemma is not resolved. That's why
they need some "rules of engagement", that is, a set of guidelines
that could give meaning and (moral and/or legal) justification for their
behaviour in given situations (especially, the act of killing);
(3) The Way I perceive the Other: According to Levinas, the absolutely
Other is the Otherness. The Otherness is infinitely transcendent. The Other is
infinitely different from me. I cannot circumscribe the contents of Otherness
through my own categories. The Otherness cannot be limited by my own thinking.
The Otherness is the absolute newness. Being is being for the otherness[19].
Practically speaking, how could we use our perception of the Otherness in a
cross-cultural dialogue? According to Harris and Moran (1991), the following
attitudes should be developed in order to "deflate the stress and tension
of cultural shock": (1) being culturally prepared; (2) learning local
communication complexities; (3) mixing with the host nationals (socialization);
(4) being creative and experimental (daring to risk, try and learn); (5) being
culturally sensitive (awareness of customs and traditions); (6) recognizing
complexities in host cultures; (7) perceiving self as bearer of cultural
traits; (8) being patient, full of understanding for hosts/others (tolerance,
flexibility); (9) being most realistic in our expectations; (10) accepting the
challenge of cross-cultural experiences[20].
In doing so, we are letting others expressing their reality, out of their
cultural and/or religious roots;
(4) The Way I am Working for Mutual Understanding: we cannot
understand the other if our pre-conceptions are purely arbitrary, said the
German philosopher Hans-Georg Gadamer (1900-2002). Understanding the other
implies: (a) to agree on the object: we must deal with the same object.
Otherwise, we will never be able to reach mutual understanding; (b) to identify
the other's view or opinion on the object; (c) to identify the historical
horizon in which a given tradition is rooted: every object comes from a given
tradition. Such tradition has an historical horizon as an answer that was given
to an historical question: any opinion is an answer to an historical question.
It could provoke a philosophical questioning when we are now looking at the
object itself and the tradition in which it is grounded. According to Gadamer
(1960), any process of building a horizon of present is basically linked to the
horizon of the past. In other words, we cannot elaborate a contemporary horizon
in our "here-and-now situation" without referring to the past
conditionings of our thought and action[21].
The Swiss Catholic theologian Hans Küng (1928-
) tried to develop a new “world ethic” that makes basic links between
the paradigm of the past (the past which is still present in our life), the
requirements of the present (the transitory present) and the possibilities of
future (the future which is already present). In the context of an
inter-religious dialogue, Küng said that we should manifest two basic
attitudes: (1) being loyal to our own religious faith; (2) being open-minded in
front of others[22];
(5) My Attitude of Tolerance and Respect For Others: respecting
someone is recognizing that he (she) is a human being (and not a sub-human). It
thus implies to admit that he (she) has a transcendental dignity, that dignity
we cannot override without denying humanity as such. Human dignity reveals a
basic equality of human beings. Moreover, respecting someone is also showing
that we have a minimum "consideration" for him/her. Consideration for
others is going over the recognition of their dignity. It presupposes an
attitude of openness that characterizes our state of mind : to be open
to anything we could find out in the others' experience or self. Respect for
others is itself a condition for the actualization of some values and virtues.
For instance, we cannot practice justice without respecting all people and
individuals. We cannot feel compassion for suffering people without fully
respecting them as persons. The German theologian and philosopher Nicholas of
Cues (1401-1464) said that only cultural and religious diversities led to wars,
cruelties and persecution. Such diversities are rooted in the history of
peoples and cultures[23].
De Cues was then promoting mutual respect and tolerance. Tolerance and respect
for each other requires a cross-cultural awareness from all parties. According
to Connerley and Pedersen (2005), such leader's awareness includes the
following elements:
« (1) an
ability to recognize direct and indirect communication styles; (2) a
sensitivity to nonverbal cues; (3) an awareness of cultural and linguistic
differences; (4) an interest in the culture; (5) a sensitivity to the myths and
stereotypes of the culture; (6) a concern for the welfare of persons from
another culture; (7) an ability to articulate elements of his/her own culture;
(8) an appreciation of the importance of multicultural teaching; (9) an
awareness of the relationships between cultural groups; (10) an accurate
criteria for objectively judging "goodness" and "badness"
in the other culture »[24].
(6) The Way I Initiate a Moral Dialogue with my Foreign Partners:
any dialogue presupposes an attitude of mutual respect and honesty. We must be
open-minded, so that we should not have any kind of moral certainty. Otherwise,
any discussion about ethical issues will never be possible. It does not mean
that we don't have moral convictions and values. Rather, it means that we are
not ready to impose them to our partners. Does it imply that there is no
absolute or universal evil we could define? No, ethical relativism presupposes
either that there is no ultimate, universal notions of good and bad, right and
wrong, or that there is no means to find out such universal notions. Ethical
relativism is thus saying that even basic human rights can vary from culture to
culture, and that they could be negated in given civilizations because of
"cultural conditionings". Moral dialogue must recognize: (1) the
truth of ethical relativism: some ethical issues could be connected to
different rules and norms, depending on the societal culture and history; (2)
the truth of ethical universalism: basic human rights as universal norms. There
should be some evils that cannot be interpreted as a good; Miller (2004) gave
the example of Nazism. According to Tsutsumibayashi (2005), it is very important
to distance the inter-civilizational dialogue from some political ends: we
could reach that end in creating shared moral values (share ethics) among
peoples of various nations and cultures; it should a "world ethics"
that will have political effects but that should never be subjected to a prior
political manipulation[25];
(7) My Ability to Question Myself about Values and Practices in our
Globalized World: Gadamer (1960) said that the act of questioning
ourselves implies the knowledge of the "not-knowing", that is, the
awareness that we do not know a lot about the object of our questioning.
Questioning ourselves is searching for truth and accepting to be part of an
authentic dialogue with others[26].
Within the process of questioning, there is both a challenge and a danger: the
challenge to overcome the pitfalls of ethnocentrism, and the danger to loose
our own existential security. Such personal questioning has to circumscribe the
areas of tolerance and those behaviours that cannot be tolerated because they are
negating humanity as such. In other words, to be tolerant is not to tolerate
everything. Basic human rights have to be safeguarded (ethical universalism),
while other apparently questionable behaviours should be placed in their
cultural/religious context (ethical relativism). Ethical discernment is the way
to distinguish both kinds of ethical issues. The ability to question ourselves
about values and practices is a condition to have an authentic search for the
ultimate truth. The authenticity of the existential quest for truth presupposes
that the individual is not considering that he/she is infinite, but rather that
he (she) is accepting his/her own existential finitude. Authentic being is the
being recognizing its own finitude and "having-to-die" condition[27].
Conclusion
How could we institutionalize
ethical leadership and favour a cross-cultural/inter-religious dialogue in the
military context? The answer to that crucial question has a twofold dimension:
(1) the impact of training sessions on the individual abilities to participate
in a cross-cultural/inter-religious dialogue; (2) the necessity to initiate
cultural changes within the military organizational culture.
(1) Setting up Conferences and Training Sessions about Ethics and
Cross-Cultural/Inter-Religious Dialogue in the Military Context: Three steps could be considered
here:
(a) Setting up Military Conferences
on Ethics, and the Cross-Cultural/Inter-religious Dialogue;
(b) Giving specific training
sessions for all military officers: how to make a
cross-cultural/inter-religious dialogue successful?
(c) Encouraging University
professors, research assistants and graduate students to be involved in
specific training sessions or Conferences.
(2) Creating Cultural Changes within the Organizational Culture of a
Given Army: Two
steps could be considered:
(a) Analyzing various changes within
the military culture: updating the contents of such military culture in a given
army; being pro-active in face of contemporaneous problematic situations;
(b) Dealing with cultural and
religious diversity issues among the troops: it would thus require training
sessions for improving the way the challenge of a cross-cultural and
inter-religious dialogue is addressed.
NOTES
[1] ARISTOTLE, Politics, book, VII, chapter 2, 1324b.
[2] ARISTOTLE, Nichomachean Ethics, Book II, 1103a14-b8.
[3] PLATO, Laws, Book I.631.
[4] Pauline KAURIN, "A Question of
Loyalty: Two Rival Versions of Moral Education in the Military", The Joint
Services Conference on Professional Ethics, 1999, 18 p.
[5] Yedidiah GROLL-YA’ARI, «Toward a
Normative Code for the Military », Armed
Forces and Society, vol. 20, no 3, Spring 1994, p. 457-471.
[6] Rollo MAY, The Meaning of Anxiety,
[7] ARISTOTLE, Nicomachean Ethics, book 3, 1117a30-b22.
[8] ARISTOTLE, Nicomachean Ethics, book 3, 1116b25-1117a25.
[9]
[10] Don SNIDER, John NAGL and Tony
PFAFF, "Army Professionalism, Military Ethic, and Officership in the 21st
Century", The Joint Services
Conference on Professional Ethics, 2000, 30 p.
[11] Michel DION, Le leadership éthique dans les organisations, Sherbrooke, Éditions GGC, 2005.
[12] James H. TONER, « Educating
for «Exemplary Conduct» », Air &
Space Power Journal, vol. 20, no 1, Spring 2006, p. 18-26.
[13] James H. TONER, "Mistakes in
Teaching Ethics", Airpower Journal,
vol. 12, no 2, Summer 1998, p. 45-51.
[14] John Stuart Mill (1806-1873) tried
to elaborate qualitative differences between given pleasures, so that some
pleasures would be substantially more important than others (John Stuart MILL, On Liberty and Utilitarianism, New York,
Bantam Books, 1993). The problem is to find out theoretical grounds for such
hierarchy of pleasures.
[15] Eugene J. FISHER, "The
Inter-religious Dimensions of War and Peace", Education for Peace. Testimonies from World Religions (H. Gordon
and L. Grob, eds.), Maryknoll, Orbis Books, 1987, p. 21.
[16] E. M. WORTEL and J.P.M.
SCHOENMAKERS, "Teaching Military Ethics. Personal Development versus Moral
Drill", The Joint Services
Conference on Professional Ethics,
[17] Michel DION, L'être en quête de vérité, Sherbrooke, Éditions GGC, 2006.
[18] According to Sartre, we are
constructing ourselves through the adherence to a given morality; we are
creating our own values, since there is no "a priori" meaning for
human existence. Human values are the meaning of life we have chosen (Jean-Paul
SARTRE, L'existentialisme est un
humanisme,
[19] Emmanuel LEVINAS, Totalité et
infini. Essai sur l'extériorité,
[20] Philip R. HARRIS and Robert T.
MORGAN, Managing Cultural Differences.
High-Performance Strategies for a
[21] Hans-Georg GADAMER, Vérité et méthode. Les grandes lignes d'une herméneutique philosophique, Paris, Collection "L'ordre philosophique", Éditions du Seuil, 1976 (1960), p. 105, 134-135, 143, 145, 147, 223.
[22] Hans KÜNG, Global Responsibility. In Search of a New World Ethic,
[23] NICOLAS DE CUSE, La paix de
la foi, Sherbrooke, Centre d'études de
[24] Mary L. CONNERLEY and Paul B.
PEDERSEN, Leadership in a Diverse
Multicultural Environment. Developing Awareness, Knowledge, and Skills,
[25] Ken TSUTSUMIBAYASHI, "Fusion
of Horizons or Confusion of Horizons? Intercultural Dialogue and its
Risks", Global Governance, no
11, 2005, p. 103-114.
[26] GADAMER, Vérité et méthode (1960), p. 212-213.
[27] Martin HEIDEGGER, Being and Time,